Humanities 2014, 3, 415–441; doi:10.3390/h3030415
OPEN ACCESS
humanities
ISSN 2076-0787
www.mdpi.com/journal/humanities
Article
The New Humanities Project—Reports from Interdisciplinarity
Mauro Bergonzi 1, Francesco Fiorentino 2, Domenico Fiormonte 3,*, Laura Fortini 4,
Ugo Fracassa 4, Michele Lucantoni 5, Massimo Marraffa 5 and Teresa Numerico 5
1
2
3
4
5
Dipartimento di Scienze Umane e Sociali, Università degli Studi di Napoli “L’Orientale”, Palazzo
Giusso, Largo S. Giovanni Maggiore, 30-80134 Napoli, Italy; E-Mail:
[email protected]
Dipartimento di Lingue, Letterature e Culture Straniere, Università Roma Tre, Via del Valco di San
Paolo, 19-00146 Roma, Italy; E-Mail:
[email protected]
Dipartimento di Scienze Politiche, Università Roma Tre, Via G. Chiabrera, 199-00145 Roma, Italy
Dipartimento di Studi Umanistici, Università Roma Tre, Via Ostiense, 234-00146 Roma, Italy;
E-Mails:
[email protected] (L.F.);
[email protected] (U.F.)
Dipartimento di Filosofia, Comunicazione e Spettacolo, Università Roma Tre, Via Ostiense,
234-00146 Roma, Italy; E-Mails:
[email protected] (M.L.);
[email protected] (M.M.);
[email protected] (T.N.)
* Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mail:
[email protected];
Tel.: +39-06-5733-5372; Fax: +39-06-5733-5280.
Received: 9 June 2014; in revised form: 4 August 2014 / Accepted: 14 August 2014 /
Published: 4 September 2014
Abstract: New Humanities is an international research and teaching project promoted by
an interdisciplinary group of people from five different faculties and departments based at
the University of Roma Tre. Initially set up as a forum for academic dialogue between the
humanities and the sciences (including social sciences), the project became a transition
space and platform for experiencing new research methodologies and teaching curricula
that would question the present epistemological order of the European university system.
In order to develop this approach, we have organized our work around a number of
interdisciplinary clusters, each describing an epistemological node. In this paper we will
discuss five interconnected case studies that emerged from an active collaboration between
scientists and humanists. The first node, Protocols of Vision, investigates the cognitive
nature of sensory perception and the different forms of knowledge it produces—empirical,
artistic, and scientific. Memory: Mathematics, Computer Science, and Literature recapitulates
many of the different threads in these discussions by exploring the interdependencies
between the various kinds of memory: from external to subjective memory, from storage
Humanities 2014, 3
416
tools and techniques of self-construction to the invariance of mathematical structures. The
third node, Signs and Bodies between Digital and Gendering, reflects on the problematic
relationship between digital media and literary and linguistic gendering. Narrative Identity:
Nature, Ontogeny and Psychopathology critically re-examines the main concepts and
theories concerning the nature, ontogeny, and pathologies of the autobiographical self or
narrative identity. Finally, the last node, Contribution of Quantum Physics to the Idea of
Consciousness is a cross-cultural investigation into the phenomenon of consciousness
tackled from the points of view of quantum field theory and ancient Indian philosophy.
Keywords: new humanities; cognitive studies; memory; computer science; literature;
narrative identity; digital gendering; consciousness; quantum physics
1. Introduction
“All the so-called visual media turn out, on closer inspection, to involve the other senses (especially
touch and hearing). All media are, from the standpoint of sensory modality, ‘mixed media’. The
obviousness of this raises two questions: (1) why do we persist in talking about some media as if they
were exclusively visual? Is this just a shorthand for talking about visual predominance? […] (2) Why
does it matter what we call “visual media”? Why should we care about straightening out this
confusion? What is at stake?” [1].
This passage is taken from W. J. T. Mitchell’s essay There Are No Visual Media, important not only
in terms of media theory, but also because the reasoning at work here can be applied to the order of
savoirs too. The practices of knowledge are always trans-disciplinary in the sense that they involve
contexts, methods, and instruments institutionally assigned to different disciplines. Academic disciplines,
in the last thirty or forty years, have been changing their self-representation, showing less cohesion and
a tendency to move from the notions of “discipline” and “canon” to practices based on collaboration
around problems, i.e., “in clusters that may be too short-lived to be institutionalized into departments
or programs or to be given lasting disciplinary labels” ([2], p. 819).
In dealing with what appears to be obvious, and increasingly so, certain questions keep coming up,
and we should welcome them: why do we continue to conceal this obviousness? Why do we persist in
speaking of clear-cut disciplines, albeit indirectly (while actually yearning for interdisciplinary practices)?
The same aspect applies to, and especially so, the well-known distinction between the so-called
two cultures, between humanities and sciences (a dichotomy that later degenerated into biased
expressions such as “soft and hard sciences”, etc.). It is a distinction that became institutionalized in
the late 19th century with the creation of two orders of knowledge to maintain a clear separation. One
of the intellectual figures behind this operation was Wilhelm Dilthey. Distinguishing between
Naturwissenschaften, i.e., the natural sciences and Geisteswissenschaften, the science of the spirit or
humanistic sciences, he established an essential difference between two objects and two methods that
in fact have nothing, which is clearly distinguishable [3].
Dilthey sees the object of humanistic sciences—man and his historical-social environment—as
basically defined by its historicity and their knowledge modality by a hermeneutic process of
Humanities 2014, 3
417
comprehension, a Verstehen, i.e., a process of construction of sense and significance in which
subjectivity is allowed to participate. Comprehension takes place via an active projection of one’s own
experience and leads to a restructuring of the Self. The other, the extraneous, is understood (in the
sense of Latin cum-prehendere, “to seize”), i.e., inserted and made to act in its own space and time.
The natural sciences are just the opposite. Here, we do not have construction, just the discovery of a
given reality, the natural, and its laws. Their mode of knowledge is an Erklären, an explanation of that
which, in nature, is given and has only to be clarified. Natural phenomena are explained when they
reflect a general law, understood as eternally valid. This is the ideal of an objective knowledge, which
would like to abstract from subjectivity and temporality, which postulates a neutrality of the subject of
knowledge as well as an immutability of the object. It is the attempt to create a territory of knowledge
detached from temporality and subjectivity, and freed of the struggles of hermeneutic understanding as
to legitimate only an interpretation, which presents itself as a scientifically given reality.
This “fiction” started tottering some time ago. For some time we have known that hermeneutics
cannot be confined to the examination of cultural phenomena, that even the data we retrieve from
nature imply an interpretation, that no object can be freed of temporality and the localized nature of
knowledge, no examination can be considered irrespective of the analysis of subjects of knowledge
and the conditions of its production, representation, circulation, and reception. That no perspective is
exempt from the hermeneutic circle, that every piece of data, everything, every observation is always
linked to a pre-comprehension. This is also true—Dilthey had already said this—for the natural
sciences too. Though not embracing necessarily a post-modern vision, it would appear difficult to
release data from their interpretation. It is just this—and not just today—that humanistic knowledge
insists upon recalling. And it is just for this reason that it is in crisis and under attack [4], deprived of
its legitimacy precisely because it endangers this old distinction, which holds its critical capacity in
check. Thus, the distinction between scientific and humanistic knowledge still remains active; it is still
to be deconstructed via cognitive practices, which draw the most radical consequences from the
wavering of this distinction.
New Humanities is an international research project, which has been created to work in this
direction. Thus, not a reflection upon the crisis or sense of regret about an asset legitimized by the
powers of the past, but a new research model and, as a result, an educational one—a new epistemic for
a new paideia. And the construction of this new cultural code cannot be considered irrespective of the
establishment of new relations not only between areas of knowledge but between the people and the
different cultures of the planet. There is nothing here about new ideas. Though in the West we have
preferred to ignore them, there have always existed educational experiments, which have tried to draw
the best from different traditions. In the last century the Nobel prize winner Rabindranath Tagore
founded Visva-Bharati [5] (Visva means “union”, and Bharat is India), a new concept of university
founded on certain key principles, among which the equal dignity of cultures and religions in the
world, interdisciplinarity and the idea that teacher and student decide together the time and pace of
their education [6].
We mention this institution (Nobel prize winner Amartya Sen was among his pupils) because our
project originated with the collaboration of a group of researchers, teachers, and students of Roma Tre
who wished to interpret the “crisis” of the humanities like a phase of regeneration and passage towards
a new form of human science which should: (1) acknowledge the interconnections between disciplines
Humanities 2014, 3
418
and actively recognize that “scientific practices are modeled through notions such as networks,
assemblages, experimental systems, trading zones, and so on” ([2], p. 819); (2) take up once more the
dialogue between sciences of nature and those of culture which had slackened and was then interrupted
from the 17th century on, so as to go beyond their distinction; (3) absorb analytically and
systematically the epistemic leap imposed by the digital transformation of data, knowledge and
identities in a heated analytical dialogue with those technologies which have re-defined research and
representation methodologies in all fields. We are aware that in setting up this agenda we were not
alone but had illustrious predecessors. However, a detailed discussion on the epistemological and
historical aspects of interdisciplinarity was well beyond the scope of this paper. It is worth remembering
that interdisciplinary work has encountered historically a number of practical and theoretical obstacles:
from epistemic barriers (involving “incompatible styles of thought, research traditions, techniques, and
language that are difficult to translate across disciplinary domains” ([7], p. 47) to evaluation criteria
and tenure anxiety, from the lower academic status of interdisciplinary journals to institutional,
administrative and departmental drawbacks, etc.
New Humanities has tried to bypass some of these problems by organizing clusters around specific
research themes from which we selected the present five reports. We hope the differences in style,
length, and content of these reports will be justified by the heterogeneity of the case studies and the
events from which they originated. In the last two years the research group has organized about fifteen
seminars, meetings, conferences, and book presentations on seven clusters in which the research was
originally structured. Physics and sociology, biology and philosophy, mathematics and literary
criticism, computer science and history of art, are some of the areas, which have engaged in dialogue
and have been reshuffled, exploring unexpected connections or rediscovering old relations. That does
not necessarily mean that the knowledge and approaches presented are completely new or
revolutionary [8]; indeed some aspects under discussion in the essay are well established in their
disciplinary contexts. The sequence of the five reports does not follow the original chronological order,
but it lays down a research path which we think has a main theme, that of rethinking the relation and
dialogue between body and mind, between perception and consciousness. In the background we find
the question of the digital transformation of knowledge and cultural and cognitive representations, a
common ground for all the contributions. We hope our selection will demonstrate that these challenges
cannot be met by single discipline alone.
Clusters edited by Ugo Fracassa and Teresa Numerico are dedicated respectively to the problem of
vision and that of memory, both involving a background of algorithms and digital representations.
Following this, we have the cluster edited by Laura Fortini on the questions, which the digital raises
about bodies and the signs which represent them, and the text on narrative identity authored by
Massimo Marraffa. The last assemblage, edited by Domenico Fiormonte, Michele Lucantoni, and
Mauro Bergonzi, is the longest and probably the most challenging, as authors tried to set up a dialogue
between distant fields in the attempt to build a cross-cultural perspective on consciousness. We are
convinced that this brief core sampling in the activity of New Humanities presents trans-disciplinary
transfers and reflections that reveal, ever more fully, the transience of the confines between nature and
culture, natural sciences and humanities, producing a decentralization of the single disciplines.
Knowledge no longer appears fragmented in distinct and separate territories, but transforms into a
large inter-connective network, which constantly repositions its nodes. The challenge today is to imagine
Humanities 2014, 3
419
new models to connect cognitive horizons and production modalities of knowledge, which are with
increasingly more insistence, breaking the boundaries of the single disciplines in which they have been
confined. According to the Ancient Indian wisdom (not “philosophy” in the Western sense), “innovating
means to expand our consciousness of what reality is and has never ceased to be” ([9], p. 18). This is an
interesting “extracting”, not-accumulative idea of progress (expanding consciousness, not accumulating
books or building monuments, etc.) that may help us also to think about scholarship, and science in
general, in a new way.
2. Seeing, Knowing, Recognizing: Protocols of Vision in Science, Art, and Life
The seminar “Protocols of Vision”, organized at the University of Roma Tre on 15 March 2013,
dealt with questions concerning the cognitive nature of sensorial perception and the different forms of
consciousness—empirical, artistic, scientific—which might be the outcome. In particular, thanks to the
contributions of three scholars, Michele Rucci (Boston University), Lucia Foglia (McGill University),
and Ugo Fracassa (Roma Tre), from different disciplines (computer science, philosophy and literary
theory) the idea that there exists a simple “seeing” is challenged. The three approaches
converge ultimately upon the case study provided by the famous portrait The Afghan Girl by the
American photographer Steve McCurry for the “National Geographic” in 1984. To consider the
knowledge-recognition dialectic in the light of visual perception it seemed it might be useful to focus
on the point at which visual perception and esthetic experience converge.
Artificial intelligence systems are now able to emulate the logical-deductive processes that are
characteristic of humans. Examples range from the IBM computer that beat the chess champion Garry
Kasparov in 1997, to programs now available on any smartphone. However, similar progress has not
occurred in the field of visual perception. What are the principles hidden by biological vision systems
that have not allowed their replication in machines?
Perception, like other vital functions, in man, has much more sophisticated procedures than those in
other living species, though the functional objectives remain the same, vision for example. Such
complexities are not to be explained by the structure of the sensory system, which is at times
more developed in other living organisms than in humans. It derives from the filtration of the
perceptions at the level of a nervous system that does not limit itself to accepting them as they are
when it receives them.
In humans, sensory information processing displays characteristics that seem unique: it does not
involve the nervous system alone, and information dependent upon the body and its interactions with
the environment play a guiding role. Sensory information processing is also affected by personal
constructs, learning history, and exposure to particular cultural stimuli. Though these influences do not
cancel out the salience and richness of the incoming sensory stimuli, they do have an impact, to a great
extent, upon how neural information processing is achieved. Rather than being a mere description of a
“given”, perception always unfolds within a particular frame of reference and involves skills and
knowledge that go beyond the mere reception of an external stimulus. We cannot really say that the
objects we see are “facts”, given, once and for all, as they are mentally constituted within the
theoretical framework that expresses them.
Humanities 2014, 3
420
The ways in which we perceptually experience the world pose a challenge to the notions of “pure
perception” and “informational encapsulation”. After all, it is the very organization of the visual areas
that allows for numerous feed-forward and back projections and the existence of a cross-talk between
cortical and non-cortical regions which shapes and modulates how information is processed. Thus,
understanding the nature of perception means going beyond the neural activation of specific visual
areas, and taking into account the non-visual information that modulates how perception is achieved.
In other words, a visual system does not function independently of the individual who embodies it, and
it cannot be taken to be isolated from cognition and action. Therefore, each result of our perception
requires us to take into account our individual, “egological” coordinates, i.e., the information, attitudes,
and tendencies that the individual possesses on the basis of his previous experiences and the history of
his mind.
Culture too, understood as a set containing knowledge, beliefs, norms, and values, may affect the
way perception is achieved (in terms of accuracy and speed). Empirical evidence in support of cultural
variation has shown, for example, that North-American populations tend to display more attention to
focal objects and their features and neglect or ignore the interdependence existing between a given
object and its surrounding context, thus deploying a holistic processing style. In closing, what we
visually perceive is, on the one hand, what our visual system allows us to see, and on the other, what
we “can” actually see relative to the non-visual information that interferes with and modulates sensory
information processing.
In 1986, Carlo Ginzburg recalled in a well-known essay, that the eye “is more sensitive to the
(perhaps marginal) differences between human beings than those between rocks and leaves” ([10],
p. 123): for those wondering about mental, emotional, and cultural interferences in vision, the
photographic portrait of Sharbat Gula, now a planetary icon of alterity at the end of the last
century ([11], p. 3) might now be worthy of an in-depth study. Once more in the news, with the recent
Italian exhibitions (in Perugia, Rome, and Genoa) the famous picture by the American photographer
encourages reflection about the influence on the act of seeing of culturally acquired mental
factors—including a certain post-colonial and gender deformation [12]—and raises specific questions
about the burden of these factors on the formation of each specific perception. Gula was photographed
again seventeen years after the first photograph and her life (and body) had changed entirely. She was
identified thanks to the Iris Scan (an algorithm patented by John Daugman, professor of Computer
Vision at Cambridge [13]), a practice that denies the most common and typically human practice of
recognition. Finally, in a similar perceptive adventure, the esthetic vision of the portrait intervenes, an
experience thanks to which it seems we can re-read the entire Afghan Girl affair as a symptom of a
true “western prosopagnosia” [14].
3. Signs and Bodies between Digital and Gendering
In this section we summarize the seminar that took place at Roma Tre on 13 May 2013 and
coordinated by Laura Fortini. The participants were Silvia Contarini, professor and co-director of the
Department of Italian Studies at the University of Paris Ouest Nanterre La Defense, Tiziana Terranova,
associate professor of Sociology of Communication at the University of Naples “L’Orientale”, and
Teresa Numerico, philosopher of science of the research group New Humanities.
Humanities 2014, 3
421
In the 1970s a feminist literary criticism appeared which spent a long period of time, discussing
sessuazione [15] of language in literary texts, getting involved in particular with gender connotations
of the sign. In a memorable meeting, which took place in Urbino in 1983 [16], Nancy Huston, Patrizia
Magli, Rosi Braidotti Susan Rubin Suleiman, Nancy Miller, and others discussed the possibility of
positioning sexual difference within the system of signification. In later years in Italy the discussion
continued, with, among others, Patriza Violi’s study concerning the relation between language and
sexual difference [17]. However, from the 1990s on, the increasingly elaborate presence of writing on
line seems to have concealed sessuazione of the body in the literary text, if not in the form itself of
semiotic construction. The arrival of gender and queer studies too, has led to serious doubts about the
nature/nurture binomial, analyzed by Donna Haraway [18] and Judith Butler [19], among others.
In Italy, feminist literary criticism has not become part of the academic and cultural mainstream,
despite the clear crisis in Italian literary criticism, which is by now encountering, at least as far as
traditional assumptions are concerned, obvious difficulties in determination. What exactly is critical
activity today and how should it be defined? Even though the object of critical practice changes each
time—the literary text for example—what does not seem to change is the status of criticism and thus
its epistemological crisis.
On their way out—fortunately—are those national paradigms still propped up by questions about
mother tongue languages, these too however, deeply challenged by migrant literature. What seems also
outdated is linear, consecutive historiography, given the difficulty of elaborating it according to
paradigms that cannot easily be shared by multiple and relative territorial geographies and
chronologies. And it seems equally outdated to apply the concept of literariness to hybrid and
undetermined textual forms—unless we go back to subjective aesthetic judgment. Thus, it is difficult
to find some horizon of sense, not so much for literature, which lives its own life independently of any
theoretical background, but for literary criticism understood as human science.
Contiguity with the human is in fact misleading. If the postulate is that literature and criticism are
necessary because they constitute ethical and moral horizons for the human, with respect to other
sciences, the question of the human becomes difficult to define. What do we call the animal relation
forms like those described by biologists [20] just as affective, just as relational, just as capable of
emotional learning as the human? Compared to these, the human shapes up as one element at work in
the science of consciousness, for which we might rather suggest the term “arts of consciousness”:
complex constructions of the modes of consciousness, constantly moving, dynamic, undergoing
continuous definition and redefinition of their own critical strategies.
The connection between body signs and sessuazione seems crucial in this context in questioning
and deconstructing a cultural panorama which, up to the 1900s, defined itself as universal and
monologic, abstract, and apparently objective, in other words patriarchal and which no longer
represents itself as such; the risk is being labeled as responding to a tradition and a symbolic horizon
now behind us. However, that which seemed to correspond to a certain reality, or the body, or rather
the bodies of women and men, with the advent of technologies, appears increasingly more uncertain
and difficult to determine; like textual bodies of writing [21,22] which seem, digitally, to lose material
consistency, lose a certain authorial value as a possible collocation.
Thanks to the Internet, both bodies and texts seem more uncertain and at the same time widespread,
in molecular fashion. However, this is an element of disorientation and also has propositional force, if
Humanities 2014, 3
422
we take into account the difficulty those who write online have, in achieving certainty, as indicated by
Tiziana Terranova, who, first with Corpi nella rete [23], and a careful analysis of the micro-politics of
information [24] has reflected upon the need to “think simultaneously the singular and the varied, the
common and the unique” ([24], p. 11).
With these considerations in mind, what consistency has the question of sessuazione of language
and literature? Teresa Numerico [25,26] has pointed out that already in 1991 Evelyn Fox Keller had
noted the risk, for example, in representing life as a machine: the elimination of the parturient female
in the technology of reproduction ([27], p. 179).
Here, Silvia Contarini has put the axiomatic association “women and maternity” to the test, at the
center of the current debate about assisted reproduction, with respect to the futurist texts of the 1910s
and 1920s [28]. Futurist authors anticipate the fear of machines incarnated in possible future worlds in
which we will not need women to be born: these images are useful for deconstructing apocalyptic
scenarios in which we see the intervention of machines in the reproductive possibilities of the human
race. What is different is the way this comes over in texts written by women, both futurist and
contemporaries, even at a distance of a century. On the one hand we have a hypothetical and futuristic
representation of possible emancipation from a tiring maternal role, as in the case of the futurist Rosa
Rosà (1918) [29]. On the other, the reality of a complex relation with machines, like in Lo spazio
bianco by Valeria Parrella [30], a novel dedicated to a premature birth and the complex relation a
mother mantains with the incubator bringing her daughter up.
Looking at the results of the seminar as a whole, we could say that the digital dimension challenges
bodies and signs with an intense post-human potential [31]. If the digital defines itself as the place
where texts do not have body, either textual or material, and bodies themselves seem to lose certain
connotations, literature, online or on paper, seems to maintain the capacity for naming—of use in an
attempt at defining uncertain, but also interesting, shifts in the confines of our present. Forerunners in
questions relative to the human and the post-human are writers like Clarice Lispector and her excellent
story The Passion according to GH (1964) [32], which has meant so much in the sphere of feminist
thought because of its reflections on links with the animal world [33–35]. Or a text like L’iguana by
Anna Maria Ortese (1965) [36], which investigates the obscure and uncertain confines with something
seemingly as unlike man as can be imagined, i.e., an iguana. Which means that, basically, paraphrasing
Gertrude Stein, a sign is a sign is a sign, whose corporeal articulation—gendered, human, post-human
online or on paper—is an active, unavoidable component of this present time.
4. Memory Construction: Invariants, Variability, and Media [37]
This contribution summarizes the work of the seminar “Memory: mathematics, computer science,
literature”, held on 20 November 2013 at the University of Roma Tre. Participants were Giuseppe
Longo (Centre national de la recherche scientifique-Paris) Francesco Fiorentino (Roma Tre), and the
coordinator Teresa Numerico. The idea behind the meeting was an examination of the practices of
memory in different disciplines, in the knowledge that it is the way the “data” are organized that
affects what the outcomes of the cognitive process will be [38]. Furthermore, the representation of
memory and its role in consciousness affects the perception of the historicity of scientific practices, as
well as the variability of possible outcomes. Therefore, this section will reflect upon the practices and
Humanities 2014, 3
423
policies of construction of sense through memory, in different disciplines and in relation to the uses of
conservation mediums and the transmission of consciousness.
In order to address memory from this broad and complex perspective, we involved scholars from
different fields, such as philosophy, literary theory, biology, computer science, theory of perception,
history, etc. Of course each of these areas contributed to the discourse with its research agenda and
theoretical views, and our aim could not be to merge or reduce them to a common denominator.
Perhaps the only justification for this experimental approach was that we all know that memory, as a
fundamental element for the construction of consciousness and for the reproduction of the living being,
can be many different things. It has different meanings, places, mediums, practices. So the techniques
used to study the ways it manifests itself and acts in different spheres of knowledge are different but so
too are the political uses we make of it. Therefore, it is crucial to elaborate a critical analysis of the
interdependencies between external memory and subjective memory, archiving tools and techniques of
the construction of the self, with a multiplicity of contexts and the discovery of invariances.
According to Giuseppe Longo [39,40] memory is constitutive of mathematics too, which can be
defined as the science, which deals with the invariance of structures and establishes which
transformations preserve it. Memory, as an essential part of anticipation, constitutes the maintenance
of invariance of action. Anticipation extracts the invariant character of memory from a changing
context with the aim of preserving the possibility of next action. Such a contextual meaning establishes
the conceptual constructions of mathematics not in isolation with respect to other forms of
consciousness but by attributing to the first a maximum practical and historical stability. The
recognition of the invariance of mathematical structures in the fluidity of processes has therefore a
mythopoeic nature. That is to say, mathematics can be associated with the myth in that it too is capable
of bringing together the fact of being in this world (physical) and the capacity for human
communication. The construction of invariances however requires the use of a particular type
of memory.
The mathematical invariance exists only as an intentional construction. In this sense a perfect
memory as a digital database cannot construct any invariant characteristics. The productive capacity of
recall is the present reactivation of mnestic content, which Edelman [41] describes as a situation in
which “the brain repositions itself in a living state” in the act of remembering [40]. The machine, with
its perfect “memory” can, at most, help to engage in proof-checking but in no sense does it work on the
activation of original demonstrations. Only animal memory and human deliberative capacity have the
chance to construct proof which can demand the introduction of new concepts and structures which
transcend the use of rules in a formal system. The only indispensable assumption to obtain interesting,
creative responses is the active capacity to invent the present and construct connections between the
structures of human memory [42,43].
Longo thus shows how memory is the basis of the construction of invariance in mathematics. In this
perspective, even an abstract science like mathematics has a clearly historical consistency since
knowledge is constructed via the intentional, creative, and deliberative acts of a community. Such are
mnemonic acts too.
Therefore, we cannot avoid getting to grips with the reorganization of memory produced by the new
use of this term in the sphere of the digital revolution. Human memory is multi-faceted and
multiform [44] and cannot be compared to digital memory. However, it is clear that the use of the
Humanities 2014, 3
424
same term to indicate two very distinct concepts has had an influence on the redefinition of the
so-called “family similarities” which contribute to the construction of rules for the use of the term. So
it seems also useful to reflect on the genealogical effects produced by the use of this term in the digital
machines field and the role of a linguistic habit on the semantic transformations of the initial term [45].
Personal memory is associative and reconstructive, imaginary, constantly active and dynamic.
Totally unlike the rigidity of electronic memory, which conserves every bit in an exact, inscrutable
mapping. The concept of memory in the two devices has a clearly different significance. Human
memory seems difficult to control, precisely because it is impenetrable, indeterminate, and at the same
time extremely fragile. As Wendy Chun suggests, “the memory of the machine is at the same time
incredibly precise and absolutely unstable from a technical point of view” ([46], p. 140). The opposite
of human memory, extremely solid and tirelessly deceiving. In short, the differences could not be
bigger, but we are by now used to considering digital memory as the best replacement of human
memories. The desire to stabilize the hardware leads the project to construct digital memory,
metaphorically, so that it can contain and reproduce that which it contains ([46], p. 139). The political
idea behind the digital is the stabilization of the datum, the petrification of memory in data, which are
represented as objective, neutral, elementary. “Raw data is an oxymoron” says the title of an
interesting collection of essays [47] in which the fictional nature of the raw datum is stressed.
“Facebook’s job is to improve how the world communicates”, says Zuckerberg. Projects like
Wikipedia or Google Books aim at restoring human knowledge conserved in books (Google Books),
and in the heads of the experts (Wikipedia). Google Scholar sets out to organize scientific knowledge
and make it universally accessible, and the scope of Google is “to organize the world’s information
and make it universally accessible and useful” [48].
In all these money-making projects, as in other public ones [49] it is possible to see the myth of
exhaustiveness of knowledge and the archiving of information as a “total experience”. But archives
always exist as partial and violent institutions and the present constitutes itself in opposition to these,
as Derrida sustains in Archive Fever: “The archive takes place at the place of originary and structural
breakdown of the said memory. There is no archive without a place of consignation, without a
technique of repetition, and without a certain exteriority. No archive without outside” ([50], p. 11).
It is therefore impossible to replace the function of recall and the reconstruction of the past in
memory with that of archiving without losing the function itself of archiving. Without memory,
without an outside, even the archive declines and above all loses its exteriority form, from which it
should be able to escape, which gives sense and at the same time can be transformed and recomposed
into an ever newer sense.
If libraries, archives, repositories of scientific articles, personal diaries and descriptions of collective
adventures are all consigned and imprisoned in a cloud of data (never mind if open or closed), how do
we subvert the archive and construct the history of society and knowledge? The Cloud, a shared space
but also private, where collectively we save our contents, is a perfect example of the collapse of
memory, archive and that set of rules which interpret the information, giving them a sense.
As if the theme of archiving policy did not exist, as if we might exteriorize the support and conserve
intact the practices of reminiscence, strengthening them efficiently without transforming them.
If the operation of sorting out data becomes the interpretation tout court of sense, if no datum is
able to escape the extraction of meaning activated by the algorithm thought up for the machine, then
Humanities 2014, 3
425
the crucial political question is: how can we activate the dynamics of transformations in interpretation?
No human interpreter can compete with the “interpretative” potential of the machine and no operation
of extraction of meaning of data can ever be critically checked [51]. Google Glass is another example
of the transformative perspective of memory and consequently of knowledge adopted by web
companies. The promise (or the illusion) of a new form of perception, a new form of vision that will
allow the “glasses” to see what the user sees, and to offer an interpretation or support for an
understanding of the actual vision. The offer of a unique, coherent, effective interpretation of data by a
proprietary and opaque device could change irreversibly the way we interpret and understand our
present and anticipate our future. The risk of the device however is not just to fall short of user
expectations—after all a minor problem. The real risk is that Google Glass will alter our perception
and understanding of the idea of the interpretation of the world around us, even when it fails. In fact,
the more it fails the more its influence can alter the human idea of understanding and interpreting
signs, events, and objects around us.
But history and criticism originate with the polysemic dynamics and variability of concepts and
texts, like the variability of genes which allow us a selection and conservation of the species, together
with the variability of environments and reactions to them, which allows the epigenesis of those traits,
which are more suitable for survival [20]. It is memory in its creativity and variability, which
guarantees the process of history. Memory is saved only if it erases, only if it extracts its own pathway
to sense from the sea of data in which it navigates. Human memory is very selective: it is capable of
preserving and organizing memories, by forgetting.
If the archive is universal and the answers to every question are univocal, if there is no distance
between private memory and public archive, if all we know we find in the same tested sources which
distil overall shared knowledge, then the dream of variability and multiplicity at the heart of the
hypertextuality becomes only an illusory myth and the net is lost in the delirium of omnipotence of
algorithms of ranking and sorting out of data, the fruit of machine-learning techniques.
And yet, when memory becomes public practice it is always political, even though in managing the
construction of objectivity there are now complex devices made up of the interaction between human
beings and machines of which we lose awareness in a game of cross-references and reflections which
never seem to have an end. In this assemblage—as visible as it is opaque—personal and collective
traces are activated in the comings and goings of cross-references, which transform our relation with
ourselves and with our machines for memory.
The question still awaiting a response concerns the possibility of effective action of empowerment
produced by extroflection and then collectivization of memory. No mediatic device is ever neutral with
respect to the organization and the content itself, which is traversed by them. Once more, this is a
remediation [52], but what is alive and what is dead after the migration is accomplished.
The mediums determine and organize memory and its practices, the collective and even more so the
personal. Each dominant medium with its codes imposes itself as a metaphor of memory. The
ever-present danger is that a medium might restrain and regiment memory as imaginative capacity,
which constructs knowledge about the past, necessary for the present. The danger is already to be seen
in Plato’s Phaedrus, which opposed memory understood as storehouse of data and memory as process
of reminiscence, which is always creative [53]. Plato warned that external memories could work as
Humanities 2014, 3
426
deactivators of the capacity for anamnesis. This is a reminiscence, which is accomplished through the
activity of a subject interacting with another subject in a maieutic process.
It is not by chance that Plato formulated his critique of writing in a written text, mobilized the
inter-textual vocation of literary writing against the fixity of the textual support to transform it into a
stimulus, to the extent that it draws the reader towards a memory which is outside it, in the
interaction—implicit or explicit—with other texts.
However, this implies a writing practice which awakens the awareness of its limits to make possible
the anamnesis of what is inaccessible for the writing medium itself, its code, its possibility
of representation.
Every medium has a potentially critical attitude and is capable of subverting the uses it is put to, the
practices it is implied in. And yet the medium is never neutral. The uses of a medium are not free: they
are determined, envisaged, directed by the technical structure of the medium itself. However, they are
not fixed. There is a negotiation with the medium’s technical possibilities. The medium becomes
transcendible when the experience of its mediality is produced, i.e., the limits which it imposes on the
representation and that which it excludes. The experience of mediality is always experience of what is
not graspable by the medium and by its code and this is why it does not become part of memory
handed down. But every medium has within itself the potentiality of letting us know at least the lack of
what it can no longer hold on to.
Today, this possibility seems more than ever threatened by digital media, which, in the exhibition of
an ever-present, accessible totality, obscure every absence. Everything is consigned, also in the sense
of immobilized, imprisoned in the registers of conservation and retransmitted as raw data. The capacity
to forget and select the information to which we wish to attribute sense, is nullified. And yet the
transience of the support constitutes a serious risk for the duration of this total conservation.
Therefore, more than ever we need to activate critical practices, which reveal the hidden gaps like
the outside of the archive, necessary so that memory can construct vital variation. It is necessary to
preserve the creative original action of the memory as a faculty of the imagination and the present,
which, albeit in the sphere of regulated procedures and precise bonds, does not remain subordinate to
the presumed neutrality and objectivity of the datum codified in the devices of conservation and
transmission of consciousness.
In conclusion, the work of this cluster aimed at singling out, critically, the practices of obfuscation
of memory policies in action in the use of certain devices and discovering how to escape from their
totalizing nature. The objective is still to preserve the historical, temporal, and contingent nature of
cognitive choices so as to protect their reversibility and variability. To this end, it would seem crucial
to recognize memory as a selective faculty which acts in the present, erasing more than it conserves,
maintaining the awareness of the ever-more precarious, unstable value of its outcomes.
5. Narrative Identity: Nature, Ontogeny, and Psychopathology
The aim of the research cluster “Narrative Identity: Nature, Ontogeny, and Psychopathology” was
to critically re-examine the main concepts and theories concerning the nature, ontogeny, and
pathologies of the construct of narrative identity, and in such a way, to provide researchers from
different areas with a forum for exploring this many-sided subject. What follows is a theoretical and
Humanities 2014, 3
427
empirical framework within which the interdisciplinary team of speakers, Gianluca Barbieri
(University of Parma), Erica Cosentino (University of Calabria), Francesco Ferretti (University of
Roma Tre), Pietro Perconti (University of Messina), Dolores Rollo (University of Parma), investigated
these issues during a seminar we organized at the University of Roma Tre in December 2012. This
framework consisted of a developmental story about how self-consciousness, conceived of as a
cognitively demanding form of consciousness (“narrative identity”), emerges by drawing on literatures
in cognitive sciences, dynamic psychology, text linguistics, and the philosophy of mind.
The ordinary term “consciousness” conflates two quite different kinds of psychological functions.
First, consciousness is a state of vigilance, i.e., the agent’s being actively present to the world: this is a
matter of forming first-order representations of states of affairs, which may function to guide the
agent’s behavior. Second, consciousness is self-consciousness, i.e., the agent’s being present to herself:
this is a matter of being in a higher-order mental state, namely a representational state that has a
first-order representation as its object. Studies in cognitive ethology and developmental psychology
seem to show that animals and infants under one year of age are conscious in the first-order sense of
being conscious: they are able to automatically and pre-reflexively form a series of representations of
states of affairs and operational plans of action, and hence to interact with persons and things in a
flexible but not self-conscious manner.
Only some species take a step beyond the basic interactive monitoring of the environment that
characterizes the simple, primary consciousness of all animals. They attain self-consciousness, and this
in at least two different senses.
Great apes like chimpanzees, and in our species infants from 15–18 months of age, can be said to
reach a state in which they are able to make a clear distinction between their own physical bodies and
the surrounding environment. More precisely, they first become capable of physical self-monitoring,
i.e., focusing attention on the material agent as the physical executor of actions; and then their bodily
self-monitoring comes to completion as the objectification of their own bodies (Merleau-Ponty’s corps
propre), and thus as a full-fledged bodily self-awareness [54].
In its simplest form, then, the description of the self is a description of physical identity. At an early
stage the bodily self-consciousness is likely to be structured by a non-verbal and analogic representation
of the (physical) self; but very soon it begins to be mediated by the verbal exchange with the caregiver.
In other words, in our species the “chimpanzee-style”, purely bodily self-consciousness is almost
immediately outstripped and encompassed by a form of descriptive self-consciousness that is strictly
linked to linguistic tools and social cognition mechanisms. Here begins the process leading to
self-consciousness as introspective recognition of the presence of the virtual inner space of the mind,
separated from the other two primary experiential spaces (corporeal and extracorporeal). This is
the foundation of human consciousness in the Lockean sense of the term: self-consciousness as
personal identity.
This psychological and introspective self-description is likely to take shape in the act of turning on
oneself the capacity to mind-read other people; and this is likely to occur around the age of 3–4 years
and in an interpersonal context, viz. in a relationship with the caregiver that is made of words,
descriptions, designations, evaluations of the person. Through the dialogue with the caregiver (and then
with other social partners) the 3–4 year child constructs itself by constructing its own identity, both
objective (for others) and subjective (for itself). And following G. H. Mead’s well-known lesson, we are
Humanities 2014, 3
428
able to say that the identity-for-itself largely derives from the identity-for-others; viz. we see ourselves,
and define ourselves, in the first place introjecting the way in which others see and define us [55].
This transition from a bodily and social identity to an introspective one is not an all-or-nothing
issue: it gradually takes place in an interplay of mind-reading [56] and linguistic-narrative capacities
modulated by socio-cultural variables [57,58]. The child who at 3–4 years of age turns his third person
mind-reading capacities upon himself under the influence of caregivers’ mind-related talk, at around
4–5 years of age begins to grasp his subjective identity as rationalized in terms of autobiography. This
is “narrative identity”, i.e., a cognitive structure that can provide the jumble of autobiographical
memories “with some semblance of unity, purpose, and meaning” ([59], p. 527). Research findings
show that the complexity and coherence of this structure increase during adolescence until early
adulthood [60]. This raises the question of what kind of narrativism is involved here [61].
In this process of narrative self-construction there is an essential psychodynamic ingredient.
Dynamic psychology and developmental psychology tell us that affective growth and the construction
of identity cannot be separated; the description of the self that from 2–3 years of age the child
feverishly pursues is an “accepting description”, i.e., a description that is indissolubly cognitive (as
definition of self) and emotional-affective (as acceptance of self). In brief, the child needs a clear and
consistent capacity to describe itself, fully legitimized by the caregiver and socially valid. On the other
hand, this will continue to be the case during the entire cycle of life: the construction of an affective
life will always be intimately connected to the construction of a well-defined and interpersonally
valid identity [62].
We believe the main result of the research cluster, which is continuing to develop its ideas, was to
highlight the need for a synthesis of different perspectives on self-consciousness as narrative self. In
the current debate the theme of self-consciousness tends to be approached with a limited focus; and
hence the different facets of self-consciousness (its non-conceptual versus higher-level forms, or its
inter-subjective and temporal aspects) remain relatively isolated [63]. We, at the Rome seminar, made
an effort to make up for this thematic isolation and achieve a more integrated view, putting together
perspectives that are usually kept separate. So the contributions were informed by philosophy of mind,
cognitive sciences, text linguistics, but were also receptive to some aspects of psychoanalysis in an
attempt to get the most out of the psychodynamic notion of a defense mechanism.
6. The Contribution of Quantum Physics to the Idea of Consciousness: A Culturally In-Between
Hypothesis [64]
We are presenting here a summary of the main contributions to the seminar which took place at
Roma Tre on the 18 September 2103 with the participation of Emilio Del Gudice, quantum phycisist
(Istituto di Fotonica e Nanotecnologie - Milan), Massimo Marraffa (Roma Tre), philosopher of science
and historian of psychology, Mauro Bergonzi (University of Naples, “L’Orientale”), historian of
Indian religions and philosophies, and Michele Lucantoni (Roma Tre), philosopher of biology. Unlike
the other reports in this collection, the complex nature of the topic did not allow us to write an
individual summary. The objective of the seminar was to initiate a dialogue, not to construct a
consistent discourse which would necessarily have brought about an improper amalgamation of ideas
and disciplines which are significantly different, as well as distant, over time and space. The intention
Humanities 2014, 3
429
behind the project was to examine the idea of consciousness, which emerges from a number of Emilio
del Giudice’s writings. This idea was then associated with the model of consciousness elaborated by
the quantum phycisist Amit Goswami (see Michele Lucantoni’s conclusions) who explores in
detail the links between quantum mechanics and ancient Indian sapiential thought, especially the
advaita-vedānta school (one of the six darshanas or theoretical-interpretative systems which derive
from the Veda, considered “orthodox” by Hinduism). The two physicists start off differently, but come
to the same deep ontology: a unique universal consciousness. We have decided to connect Goswami
and Del Giudice by involving Mauro Bergonzi, a scholar of the Vedanta philosophical tradition, in
order to explore the connections between Quantum Physics and the Non-dualist Indian Thought [65].
So, where does consciousness reside? What does that which Francis Crick defined “the last great
mystery of science” consist of [66]? And above all who will have the last word about that personal
experience which seems to contain the whole universe? The basic assumption, shared by all the
participants, is that since any appeal to quantitative criteria would inevitably fail, a plurality of voices
might be the only plausible, desirable way to approach the “truth” concerning consciousness. In this
exploration we will discover that the thousand-year old path, which unites the two parallel quantum
edges is the non-dualist sapiential thought conserved in the vedic Upaniṣads. These ancient Indian
spiritual, philosophical, and mystical writings seem to have foreseen, at the dawn of every gnosiology,
the most profound aspects of the relation between consciousness and reality.
6.1. Quantum Field Theory and the Physics of Living Matter: A Hypothesis on Physical Phenomena
Let’s start with a metaphor about the development of science in recent millennia. The metaphor
consists of a comparison between this development and that of a child when someone gives him a toy.
Science is the child and the toy is nature. At the beginning the child plays by following the
instructions, then if he is smart enough, the child wants to know what it is like inside and breaks it.
Once the toy has been smashed into hundreds of pieces, most of the time the child stays there looking
at it. There is also the chance that the child will try to re-assemble it, giving him a toy, which is like the
other one because it is made up of the same pieces. So there are three phases of approaching the toy,
which correspond exactly to the three stages of science. At the beginning, human beings looked around
nature and began to make catalogues, a list of all that exists—a gigantic challenge. It is necessary to
establish correlations empirically, which is hardly a simple task. For example, the stroke of genius in
understanding how babies are born: establish a correlation between a sexual act taking place one day
and the birth of a baby nine months later is by no means a trivial matter—it means following a long
distance concatenation of cause and effect.
The first stage in science is by no means a simple one and in fact it has taken millennia—just think
of the time spent grasping the irregularities of all celestial motion. This phase lasted, at least in the
western world, up to the Renaissance. After the Renaissance, another approach took shape, which
consisted of chopping nature up into tiny pieces. Clearly, nature dismantled is no longer nature:
dismantling nature is an act of death, you kill the living being to see what’s inside—death as an
essential part of life. We discovered that the living being is made up of cells, which are in turn made
up of nucleus and cytoplasm. Then molecules arrived, atoms, protons and electrons, then quarks—no
Humanities 2014, 3
430
longer to be broken down—in an organism formed as a “matrioshka”. We now find ourselves on the
threshold of the third phase, which involves recomposing it all and seeing how it holds together.
Quantum mechanics was born exactly 113 years ago. What is the difference between quantum
physics and classical physics? How did we come to recognize that classical physics was not enough to
explain certain phenomena? The criterion consists of taking the reasoning behind previous physics to
extreme consequences. This is why theoretical physics is important: with rigorous logic we can derive
all the consequences of principles. When we enter a blind alley we are forced to begin a conceptual
revolution. Quantum mechanics thus originates with a logical crisis in classical physics. We see that it
is wrong to consider bodies as inert and separate, that they can receive energy only, exclusively, from
the interaction with other bodies. Therefore we have a spontaneous fluctuation of all bodies in
connection with their interaction with the vacuum and since the vacuum is everywhere, this is an
interaction we cannot avoid. Thus, if this is the case, it means we cannot make use of an isolated body,
the principle, which is behind the conceptualization of classical physics.
Nobody can any longer be isolated because thanks to its fluctuations in the vacuum it is
constantly communicating with other bodies, there is always an interaction. For almost a century, this
result—which is a revolution in thinking—has gone unobserved and has been hidden behind the idea
of the existence of paradoxes, interpretations, which attributed to the observer and his interaction, the
reason behind the spontaneous fluctuability of bodies. The observer, perturbing: the atom is small, the
observer is large, the latter cannot do otherwise—he perturbs. However, macroscopic quantum systems
like superconductors have been discovered. I might have a superconductor cable a hundred miles long
and the size ratios invert (the observer becomes microscopic). Thus, we do not have interaction with
the observer, but rather an interaction with the vacuum in which the body is exposed to the fluctuations
of all the other bodies of the universe. We are approaching our conclusion.
To sum up, from a formal point of view, the results of quantum mechanics we should recall Bell’s
theorem: he was a physicist who posited in terms of formal logic the outcomes of quantum mechanics.
He maintains: “The following set of three statements is logically incompatible, so one of the three just
has to go: (1) physical reality is described by quantum mechanics; (2) physical reality is susceptible to
an objective description—in that it is independent of the observer; (3) physical reality is describable as
a set of localized events in space and time. These three statements cannot, all three, stay together” [67].
Einstein, who is one of the fathers of quantum mechanics and predicted the connections formalized
by Bell, was of course a brilliant scientist but he did not go that far ahead. For Einstein, reality had to
be objective and at the same time localizable [68]. He was ironic about the fact that if, in order to
understand an object it is also necessary to know what is happening in the constellation Andromeda,
then science is over. Science becomes possible only when it can localize objects: he was solidly bound
to objectivity. His statement implied the falsity of quantum mechanics, which becomes only an
approximation to reality, while awaiting a truer theory.
So Einstein’s party, which remains a minority, brings down the first of the three statements. Niels
Bohr and the entire Copenhagen school, which dominated 20th century physics, brings down the
second statement concerning objectivity. He argued that since quantum mechanics is true and remains
a problem of localizability, one would say that objects, even before they are localized, produce these
incredible fluctuations which lead to indeterminism [69]. Suppose I have a boat and I do not want to
admit the relation with far-off maritime motions, I can declare that sometimes the boat itself produces
Humanities 2014, 3
431
rash movements. This is a form of blindness because it takes account of apparent objectivity but does
not go very far. It is David Bohm who drops the third statement. And he argued that it is not true that
we can conceive of reality as a set of separate objects [70]. This is the most important point. Given the
fluctuation of every body, the body produces an electromagnetic potential, which travels afar and
connects the other bodies. The fluctuation of a body is immediately communicated to other bodies,
which produce a sort of collective dance. Naturally the extent of these oscillations can vary in size so
that the experimental consequences can also be small, because they are covered by environmental
factors, which is why at times classical physics, especially when it works at high temperatures, clearly
represents reality without appealing to quantum mechanics because the fluctuations produced by the
thermal agitation impact are large enough to cover micro-fluctuation. If, however, one works at low
temperatures, these micro-fluctuations re-emerge and are observable—the reason why quantum
mechanics was discovered at low temperatures.
Once we understand the mechanism, we can make the following concluding statement. It is possible
that the different fluctuations of the different bodies reach harmonization, so that a collective
movement is created which magnifies the fluctuation as a whole. Just suppose I have a group of
singers, each one produces a whisper in phase (i.e., mutually synchronized) one with the other: in the
end a huge concert emerges. The important thing is to put one’s own fluctuations into phase.
Here, energy is of little importance. Energy exits as a final result. What is important is the rhythm,
the phase, which does not have an energetic content. If the elements in a system are in phase, this can
work with infinitesimal energy consumption. This is the principle difference between computer
and brain. The computer is made of objects, which are not in phase so that every element of the
computer, to do something, has to spend energy. However, if we used the game of spontaneous
fluctuations—which cost nothing because they are produced naturally—and we managed to pilot them
so as to produce a symphony in phase, what would emerge would be music and not the usual noise of
discordance. This is what really happens. We have seen that liquid water naturally emits a sound,
which has the structure of a musical score. This is the physical basis, which allows us to understand
how the matter, at a certain degree of development, produces a psyche. What is a psyche if not a
logos? And what is a logos if not a set of harmonized fluctuations which produce meaning?
6.2. Indian Non-Dualist Thought and Philosophical Implications of Quantum Physics
Indian non-dualism and some of the philosophical implications of Quantum Physics discussed in
this cluster seem to share the view that reality is an indivisible whole, while the perception of separate
entities is just a mental construct without any cogent ontological foundation (including the idea of an
individual “ego” dwelling “within” a single body/mind).
On the other hand, consciousness as such (not to be confused with its incidental “contents”, like
perceptions, sensations or thoughts) is a basic principle which cannot be consistently explained as the
end result of any physical or mental cause, since no “explanation” or “cause” could appear without
consciousness already being there as a precondition. So consciousness is an irreducible reality prior to
any perception, sensation or thought. Its evidence is doubtless, for at any time anybody can verify with
absolute certainty (through one’s own direct experience) that he/she exists and is aware.
Humanities 2014, 3
432
Therefore, since all phenomena can be perceived, known or explained if and only if consciousness
is already there, it is impossible to regard consciousness as the end product of any other phenomenon
without bumping into an epistemological paradox.
Moreover, according to non-dualism, “consciousness” and “world” are just two different descriptions
of one and the same indivisible reality (respectively in terms of the “first” or of the “third” person),
while the alleged separation between “subject” and “object” is nothing but an illusory mental
construct. This stance could encourage new perspectives in the current philosophical debate
engendered by the amazing discoveries in the fields of Quantum Physics and Cognitive Sciences.
The Sanskrit word advaita means “non-dualism” and points to the simple fact that in reality
separation does not exist: there are differences, endless differences, but no actual separation. If the
universe is a consistent totality, how does the perception of separate entities arise?
In perception, through names and concepts, we organize sense data in patterns that we recognize as
separate objects (houses, cars, trees, and so forth). According to philosophers like Kant and
Wittgenstein, empirical data are mainly constructed by way of conceptual thought and language.
Benjamin Lee Whorf pointed out how the grammatical structure of our mother tongue radically
influences the act of perception itself: through the naming process we arbitrarily engender an illusory
segmentation of the unified universe into a world of apparently separate entities [71]. On the basis of
this view, every experience is an interpretation of bare sense data through language, so that we cannot
perceive what we have not a word for. Moreover, all that is perceived through different names appears
as a fragmented set of discrete entities.
In Indian thought, the ancient precursor of this constructivist perspective was the concept of
nāma-rūpa. Nāma means “name” and rūpa means “perceptible form”. They are joined together in one
compound word just to emphasize that we can only perceive a form through a name. No name, no
form; many names, many forms. So our perception of a multiplicity of separate entities comes from
language, as stated in the Bṛhadāraṇyaka Upaniṣad.
Later on, Śaṅkara and advaita-vedānta maintained that the illusory perception of multiplicity arises
by superimposing concepts (stocked in memory) on “what is” now, in such a way that the indivisible
Whole appears as a mass of discrete entities limited by their names. Superimposition (adhyāsa) and
limitation (upādhi) through names and concepts are the origin of māyā’s illusion.
Therefore, through language our thought assigns specific names to various aspects of this huge,
indivisible process called “universe”, giving rise to the perception of many different forms. Each word
is like a “frame” that traces a conventional as well as arbitrary edge around some aspects of the Whole,
differentiating an “inside” as opposed to an “outside” and thus creating the illusion that a specific form
is independent and separate from all other forms identified by different names. Moreover, names are
static, incapable of capturing actual movement, just like photography, which is obliged, for example, to
show a man running by means of many different photos of men frozen in motion.
Thus, after creating an illusory multiplicity of fixed and separate entities through language, we
mistake this inadequate description of reality for reality itself, whereas the universe is just one formless
process, which appears as an amazing expanse of different, but not separate aspects.
In Indian non-dualist inquiry into our true identity (ātmavicāra or ātmavidyā), the core question is:
“Who am I?” The response can already be found in the early vedic Upaniṣads, where our true self
(ātman) is conceived as an impersonal and boundless awareness that coincides with the totality of
Humanities 2014, 3
433
being (brahman). Subject and object cannot be separated, as they are both emerging from one and the
same source: being-awareness.
By inquiring into the foundation of individual identity, through a meticulous work of reduction of
appearances, at the bottom of our immediate and direct experience we find (as both Śaṅkara and
Cartesio remark) the undeniable and certain evidence of our being and awareness (sat-cit). Without
firstly existing and being aware, we can neither perceive nor assert anything. Dualistic perception
forces an illusory gap between objects and consciousness that is deceptively considered an individual
attribute. However, according to the non-dualist perspective, both the individual ego (identified with a
single body-mind complex) and the so-called “external” objects are only different (but not separate)
contents of one and the same universal consciousness, which encompasses all existence. No content
can be perceived if primarily awareness is not there: any object appears always in, to, and
as consciousness.
In Western philosophical tradition, the Reverend Berkeley [72] had already remarked that,
according to the evidence of our direct experience, anything concerning external reality is primarily an
object of perception appearing in and as consciousness. Therefore, it is impossible to prove the
existence of a world apart from consciousness, given the inseparable and unavoidable coexistence of
both: in fact, since they always appear together, they are not two separate entities, but rather two
different aspects of the same reality.
So the boundary between subject and object is not real: the terms “consciousness” and “world” refer
only to two different perspectives (in first or third person) describing one, indivisible reality, just as
“ascent” and “descent” are two different words for the same slope, depending which way one is going.
For example, one single experience can be named either as “hearing” (if described in terms of the
subject who hears something), or as “sound” (if described in terms of the object heard). However, in the
actual experience of hearing, one cannot establish a precise boundary where sound ends “out there”
and hearing begins “in here”: in fact, there is just one, immediate experience and only later on, in order
to describe it, the thinking mind says “I heard a sound”, creating a deceptive subject/object duality.
Indian non-dualism can offer a critical contribution to the current mainstream of contemporary
neurosciences that regards the origin of consciousness as a side-effect emerging from a certain degree
of organization of a material device like the brain (wet-ware).
Firstly, due to the lack of philosophical accuracy, neuroscientists often confuse “consciousness”
with the “contents of consciousness”, the objects of consciousness (thoughts, images, perceptions,
memories) that can be observed and studied experimentally—as linked, it is true, to the functions of
the brain—with the very fact of being conscious (consciousness as such), which cannot be observed as
an object by science, since it is the source itself of any observation.
Secondly, the stance of a cause/effect relation between brain and consciousness presumes a
hierarchical causal order ranging from biological matter to consciousness: y (consciousness) depends
on x (the brain) in order to exist. But how can we assert the pre-eminence of the brain over consciousness
if it is only via the consciousness that it becomes possible to perceive and know the brain? To what
extent should we regard as “scientific” a theory asserting that y depends on x when it is also true that x
depends on y, unless we acknowledge that both of them are only two sides of the same coin?
This unsolvable epistemological loop should lead us to consider consciousness as a primary datum
of reality [73]—on a par with the fundamental forces of physics. Max Plank considered consciousness
Humanities 2014, 3
434
a fundamental principle from which matter derived [74], just as Erwin Schrödinger realized the
impossibility of attributing consciousness to matter. The classical relation between subject and object
emerged significantly renovated in Schrödinger’s words: “The world is given to me only once, not one
existing and one perceived. Subject and object are only one. The barrier between them cannot be said
to have broken down as a result of recent experience in the physical sciences, for this barrier does not
exist” ([75], p. 127).
Since we are able to observe the universe whilst we can never be apart from it, saying we observe
the world would be the equivalent of asserting that the universe watches itself via our observation. So
the universe can be regarded as a self-observing unified system: it sees itself through our eyes.
However, as G. Spencer Brown [76] properly remarks, in order to observe itself, the universe must
split itself up into at least two parts: the observer and the observed. Consequently, since the observer
cannot be observed while observing, there is always a part of the totality that remains unseen, outside
the field of observation: this unknowable remainder is consciousness itself. Here lies the paradoxical
mystery of consciousness: the very source of any knowledge is unknowable by itself.
Therefore, according to Indian non-dualist traditions, any observation or theorizing about “objective”
reality can never reach consciousness, which is the hidden background of any observing or theorizing
process. But prior to consciousness, beyond the splitting duality of subject/object, there is the
unknown Source of everything (parabrahman), the ineffable substratum of reality, which resonates
deeply, to some extent, with the concept of “vacuum” in Quantum Physics.
6.3. Amit Goswami and Quantum Consciousness: A Summary
Goswami provides science and philosophy with a new way of conceiving the puzzle of
consciousness. His proposal scourges the invisible confines of the imagination without renouncing to
the support of a measured scientific argument, to which he entrusts the force of his intuitions and faith
in universal consciousness. We use the word “faith” because Goswami seems little inclined to respect
the cornerstone of the experimental implementation proper to western science. In fact, the way in
which this revolutionary architecture of reality is presented to us provides subjectivity with a role
transcending our personality (our ego?) as to embrace that infinite coexistence of consciousness in
which the singularity embodied in individuals acts as synolon.
The monopoly of studies concerning consciousness is held by the neurosciences and the sciences of
artificial cognition [66–77]. Leaving aside for now the latter, the peak that an erudite neuroscience can
reach is a correlation between the neuronal activities and the phenomenology of experience in the first
person [78].
In the most trivial versions of the discipline, the problem of the correlation does not even present
itself since consciousness is perceived as an unwelcome guest: evolutionary tinsel qualified as
epiphenomenon—an appendix stripped of causal power—which emerges mysteriously from the work
patterns of the brain [79]. We are convinced that every epiphenomenalism is nourished by an
enigmatic paradoxality: as we fear that reality is not reflected and resolved by the system of knowledge
pleaded by a certain physics (as to save the certainty of a manageable universe), we appeal to the last
stage of magic art which is epiphenomenalism.
Humanities 2014, 3
435
The magic is in accepting that a phenomenon (consciousness/immaterial)—without a clear
definition of “phenomenon” in physics—supervenes [80] to another phenomenon (biological activity
of the brain/material) without causal prosecution or retroaction. How can a causal chain of corporeal
happenings culminate in an event, which violates the fabric of causal relations and connections
inscribed in space-time? Here we see the paradox reasserted and unveiled. To avoid asserting directly
the insufficiency of a physicalist vision, we appeal to an obvious metaphysics, which undermines the
principles of the physicalism itself! Goswami is shrewd in grasping that a vision of the world crushed
against a raw and naïve materialism ends up generating sclerotic and indirectly obscurantist
propositions, incapable of explaining the phenomena it pretends to observe. According to quantum
mechanics there are six dogmas, which mark scientific thought and which impede a clear vision of
things [81]:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
Causal determinism
The continuity of events
The locality of all objects
Clear objectivity
Monism and materialistic reductionism
Epiphenomenalism
The fact that consciousness remains tangled up in the net of these six assumptions is clear,
indisputable: where is consciousness supposed to be? If I observed my brain caught up in listening to
Miles Davis, I wouldn’t find trumpets flooding the imagination, but strips of neurons busy with a
continuous release of electro-chemicals. In this case we do not have objects of thought to be measured
and positioned in the space-temporal plot. This last observation interposes itself on the path to
consciousness like a threshold to cross. Beyond this threshold an unknown universe is waiting to be
discovered and understood. Amit Goswami builds a bridge between the old and the new: the quantum
principle of non-locality [81] seems a compulsory stage in sparking off a revolution, the protagonist being
the inseparable unity of consciousness and material, both resting upon the fullness of the vacuum.
Our question is if we will ever be ready to embrace a reality so solidly dependent on the human
presence; a reality where the abode of daily routine will be definitively assigned to the marvelous lands
of the spirit.
7. Conclusions
The aim of this work was to initiate a dialogue between disconnected areas of knowledge because
of the persistent disciplinary fragmentation inherited by educational and research institutions based on
the model established in 19th century Europe [82]. Of course this attempt, for obvious reasons, can
only be partial and epistemologically incomplete. However, we should at least trying to remedy the
damage produced by this separation on our university system and at the same time seek out for a new
model. And if a third way exists, it will be inevitably be founded on a “virtuous incompleteness” of all
epistemological models. The task of the New Humanities researcher will be to transform the isolation
of competences into a stable alliance for opening new scenarios.
Humanities 2014, 3
436
The present contribution has only begun the work in this direction. Placing studies like “Protocols
of Vision” side by side with spiritual and scientific exploration like “Contribution of Quantum Physics
to the Idea of Consciousness”, or intersect the naturalistic scenarios of “Narrative Identity: Nature,
Ontogeny and Psychopathology” with the radically different perspectives like those proposed by
“Signs and Bodies Between Digital and Gendering”, has been a healthy critical exercise for
challenging and deconstructing the old disciplinary boundaries. We think that insisting on this work of
synthesis is the only way to avoid regression to a sort of unwary society, unable to express, transmit
and criticize the complex and interconnected structure of today’s knowledge and culture.
Acknowledgments
We dedicate this work to the memory of Emilio Del Giudice, brilliant scientist and friend, who died
prematurely on the 31 January 2014. In the words of his fellow scientist Mae-Wan Ho, he was
considered by many the “Prometheus of the New Science”, a “gentle intellectual giant [who] will be
immortalized in our collective memory and in the memory of generations to come” [83]. Without his
challenging ideas and intellectual generosity, the New Humanities project would never have existed.
We are also very grateful to Antonella De Ninno for her accurate review of the transcription of
Emilio’s original conference. Translation and revision of the article is by Colin Swift.
Author Contributions
Domenico Fiormonte is first author and was responsible for editing and revising all the
contributions. Francesco Fiorentino and Domenico Fiormonte authored the “Introduction”; Ugo
Fracassa edited the Section 2 “Seeing, Knowing, Recognizing: Protocols of Vision in Science, Art and
Life”; Teresa Numerico and Francesco Fiorentino authored the Section 3 “Memory Construction:
Invariants, Variability and Media”; Massimo Marraffa wrote the Section 4 “Narrative Identity: Nature,
Ontogeny and Psychopathology”; Laura Fortini authored the Section 5 “Signs and Bodies Between
Digital and Gendering”; Domenico Fiormonte and Michele Lucantoni edited the Section 6 “The
Contribution of Quantum Physics to the Idea of Consciousness: a Culturally In-Between Hypothesis”
(except for Section 6.2 which was authored by Mauro Bergonzi).
Conflicts of Interest
The authors declare no conflict of interest.
References and Notes
1.
2.
3.
William John Thomas Mitchell. “There Are No Visual Media.” Avaliable online:
http://www.mediaarthistory.org/refresh/Programmatic%20key%20texts/pdfs/mitchell.pdf#page=1
&zoom=auto,0,798 (accessed on 25 July 2014).
Mario Biagioli. “Postdisciplinary Liaisons: Science Studies and the Humanities.” Critical Inquiry
35 (2009): 816–33.
Wilhelm Dilthey. Der Aufbau der geschichtlichen Welt in den Geisteswissenschaften (1910–1926).
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981. (In German)
Humanities 2014, 3
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
437
For an overview of the “humanities crisis” see the first part of the article by Paul Keen in the
volume I of this issue of Humanities: Paul Keen. “Imagining What We Know: The Humanities in
a Utilitarian Age.” Humanities 3 (2014): 73–87. Among the books, conferences and initiatives
devoted worldwide to the crisis of the humanistic disciplines and institutions, we would like to
mention the 4Humanities project, a web resource and community created by an international
group of “digital humanities scholars and educators to assist in advocacy for the humanities”. See
Available online: http://4humanities.org (accessed on 26 July 2014).
Visva Bharati. Avaliable online: http://www.visvabharati.ac.in (accessed on 25 July 2014).
“The Western Universities give their students an opportunity to learn what all the European
peoples have contributed to their Western culture. Thus the intellectual mind of the West has been
luminously revealed to the world. What is needed to complete this illumination is for the East to
collect its own scattered lamps and offer them to the enlightenment of the world. (…) The
Western universities have not yet truly recognized that fullness of expression is fullness of life.
And a large part of man can never find its expression in the mere language of words. It must
therefore seek for its other languages,—lines and colors, sounds and movements. Through our
mastery of these we not only make our whole nature articulate, but also understand man in all his
attempts to reveal his innermost being in every age and clime.” Rabindranath Tagore. “An Eastern
University.” In Creative Unity. New York: Macmillan, 1922. Avaliable online: http://bichitra.
jdvu.ac.in/search/english_search.php (accessed on 25 July 2014).
Jerry A. Jacobs, and Scott Frickel. “Interdisciplinarity: A Critical Assessment.” Annual Review of
Sociology 35 (2009): 43–65.
For an overview on interdisciplinary studies, see Robert Frodeman, Julie Thompson Klein, and
Carl Mitcham, eds. Oxford Handbook of Interdisciplinarity. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2010. Useful resources are also: Joe Moran. Interdisciplinarity, 2nd ed. London and New York:
Routledge, 2010; Maria Karanika-Murray, and Rolf Wiesemes. Exploring Avenues to
Interdisciplinary Research: From Cross-to Multi-to Interdisciplinarity. Nottingham: Nottingham
University Press, 2009; Julie Thompson Klein. Crossing Boundaries: Knowledge,
Disciplinarities, and Interdisciplinarities. Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1996.
Although not directly linked to our idea, we would also like to mention a project that shares
similar objectives: the online conferences project Interdisciplines. Avaliable online:
http://www.interdisciplines.org (accessed 26 July 2014).
Raffaele Torella. Il pensiero dell’India. Roma: Carocci, 2011.
Carlo Ginzburg. Clues, Myths, and the Historical Method. Translated by John Tedeschi and Anne
C. Tedeschi. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press, 1992.
Wendy S. Hesford, and Wendy Kozol. Just Advocacy?: Women’s Human Rights, Transnational
Feminism, and Politics of Representation. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2005.
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. “Subaltern studies: Decostruire la storiografia.” In Subaltern Studies.
Modernità e (post)Colonialismo. Verona: Ombre Corte, 2002, p. 136. (In Italian)
John Daugman. “How the Afghan Girl was Identified by Her Iris Patterns.” Available online:
http://www.cl.cam.ac.uk/~jgd1000/afghan.html (accessed on 25 July 2014).
Humanities 2014, 3
438
14. Dinah Zeiger. “That (Afghan) Girl! Ideology Unveiled in National Geographic.” In The Veil:
Women Writers on Its History, Lore, and Politics. Edited by Jennifer Heath. Berkeley and
London: University of California Press, 2008, p. 271.
15. I use “sessuazione”—a term which cannot be translated into English—to indicate all that which
concerns modes of representation of genres in art and literature, beginning with the experience of
the writers.
16. Patrizia Magli, ed. Le donne e i segni. Scrittura, linguaggio, identità nel segno della differenza
sessuale. Ancona: Il lavoro editoriale, 1985. (In Italian)
17. Patrizia Violi. L’infinito singolare. Considerazioni sulla differenza sessuale nel linguaggio.
Verona: Essedue edizioni, 1988. (In Italian)
18. Donna J. Haraway. Simians, Cyborg and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York:
Routledge, 1991.
19. Judith Butler. Bodies that Matter: On the Discursive Limit of “Sex”. New York and London:
Routledge, 1993.
20. Marcello Buiatti. “I linguaggi della vita.” In Canoni liquidi: variazione culturale e stabilità
testuale dalla bibbia a internet. Edited by Domenico Fiormonte. Napoli: Scripta Web, 2011,
pp. 13–26. (In Italian)
21. Laura Fortini. “Critica femminista e critica letteraria in Italia.” Italian Studies 65 (2010): 178–91.
(In Italian)
22. Laura Fortini. “Umane lettere: Dai corpi testuali agli stili dell’enunciazione.” Humanist Studies &
the Digital Age 2 (2012): 99–110. (In Italian)
23. Tiziana Terranova. Corpi nella rete. Interfacce multiple, cyberfemminismo e agorà telematiche.
Genova: Costa e Nolan, 1996. (In Italian)
24. Tiziana Terranova. Cultura del network. Per una micropolitica dell’informazione. Roma:
manifestolibri, 2006. (In Italian)
25. Teresa Numerico. Alan Turing e l’intelligenza delle Macchine. Milano: Franco Angeli, 2005.
(In Italian)
26. Domenico Fiormonte, Teresa Numerico, and Francesca Tomasi. L’umanista Digitale. Bologna: Il
Mulino, 2010. (In Italian)
27. Elisabetta Donini. Conversazioni con Evelyn Fox Keller: Una Scienziata Anomala. Milano:
Elèuthera, 1991. (In Italian)
28. Silvia Contarini. La Femme Futuriste: Mythes, Modèles et Représentations de la Femme Dans la
Théorie et la Littérature Futuristes. Paris: Presses Universitaires de Paris 10, 2006. (In French)
29. Rosa Rosà. Una donna con tre anime. Milano: Studio Editoriale Lombardo, 1918. (In Italian)
30. Valeria Parrella. Lo spazio bianco. Torino: Einaudi, 2008. (In Italian)
31. Rosi Braidotti. The Post-Human. Cambridge and Malden: Polity Press, 2013. Il postumano: La
vita oltre l’individuo, oltre la specie, oltre la morte. Traduzione italiana di Angela Balzano,
Roma: DeriveApprodi, 2014. (In Italian)
32. Clarice Lispector. A Paixao Segundo G.H., Edição Critica. Coord. Benedito Nunes. Sao Paolo:
CNPq, 1988. La passione secondo G.H. Italian Translation by Adelina Aletti, with a note by
Angelo Morino. Torino: La Rosa, 1982; Milano: Feltrinelli, 1991. (In Italian)
Humanities 2014, 3
439
33. Luisa Muraro. “Commento alla ‘Passione secondo G. H.’” Dwfdonnawomanfemme 5 (1988):
65–78. (In Italian)
34. Hélène Cixous. L’heure de Clarice Lispector. Paris: Des Femmes, 1989 (In French)
35. Donna J. Haraway. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2008.
36. Anna Maria Ortese. L’iguana. Firenze: Vallecchi, 1965; Milano: Adelphi, 1986. (In Italian)
37. This section is edited by Teresa Numerico and Francesco Fiorentino.
38. Geoffrey C. Bowker. Memory Practices in the Sciences. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005.
39. Giuseppe Longo. “Memoria e costruzione del senso in matematica.” New Humanities, 20
November 2013. Available online: http://www.newhumanities.org/seminars/20-novembrememoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/ (accessed on 25 July 2014) (In Italian)
40. Giuseppe Longo. “Synthetic Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Sciences.” Speculations,
2014, in print.
41. Gerald Edelman. The Remembered Present: A Biological Theory of Consciousness. New York:
Basic Books, 1990.
42. Giuseppe Longo. “Incompletezza.” In La Matematica. Torino: Einaudi, 2010, vol. 4, pp. 219–62.
(In Italian)
43. Giuseppe Longo. “Reflections on (Concrete) Incompleteness.” Philosophia Mathematica 19
(2011): 255–80.
44. Erich R. Kandel. In Search for Memory. The Emergence of a New Science of Mind. New York:
W.W. Norton & Company, 2006.
45. Teresa Numerico. “For a Genealogy of Digital Memory.” Available online: http://www.
newhumanities.org/seminars/20-novembre-memoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/
(accessed on 26 July 2014). (In Italian)
46. Wendy H.K. Chun. Programmed Visions: Software and Memory. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2011.
47. Lisa Gitelman. “Raw Data” Is an Oxymoron. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2013.
48. Google mission. Available online: http://www.google.com/about/company/ (accessed on 25
July 2014).
49. For example Linked Open Data by Tim Berners-Lee. Available online: http://linkeddata.org
(accessed on 25 July 2014).
50. Jacques Derrida. Archive Fever: A Freudian Impression. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1998.
51. According to Bowker and Star a system of organization of information which is neutral does not
exists. Every choice is the dynamic mirror of the interaction of the forces of power. Geoffrey C.
Bowker, and Susan L. Star. Sorting Things Out. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2000.
52. Jay D. Bolter, and Richard Grusin. Remediation: Understanding New Media. Cambridge: MIT
Press, 2000.
53. Francesco Fiorentino. “Scrittura memoria letteratura.” Available online: http://www.new
humanities.org/seminars/20-novembre-memoria-matematica-informatica-letteratura/ (accessed on
26 July 2014). (In Italian)
54. Giovanni Jervis. “The Unconscious.” In Cartographies of the Mind. Edited by Massimo Marraffa,
Mario De Caro and Francesco Ferretti. Berlin: Springer, 2007, pp. 147–58.
Humanities 2014, 3
440
55. George Herbert Mead. Mind, Self, and Society. Edited by Charles W. Morris. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1934.
56. Theory of Mind is the branch of cognitive science that investigates how we ascribe mental states
to other persons and how we use the states to explain and predict the actions of those other
persons. More accurately, it is the branch that investigates “mindreading” or mentalizing or
mentalistic abilities. These skills are shared by almost all human beings beyond early childhood.
They are used to treat other agents as the bearers of unobservable psychological states and
processes, and to anticipate and explain the agents’ behavior in terms of such states and processes.
These mentalistic abilities are also called “folk psychology” by philosophers, and “naïve
psychology” and “intuitive psychology” by cognitive scientists (see M. Marraffa. “Theory of
Mind.” The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2011. Available online: http://www.iep.
utm.edu/theomind (accessed on 26 July 2014)).
57. Dolores Rollo, and Francesca Buttiglieri. “Mother and infant talk about mental states: Systemic
emergence of psychological lexicon and theory of mind understanding.” In Processes of
Emergence of Systems and Systemic Properties: Towards A General Theory of Emergence. Edited
by Ganfranco Minati, Mario Abram and Eliano Pessa. Singapore: World Scientific, 2009,
pp. 777–86.
58. Francesco Ferretti, and Erica Cosentino. “Time, Language and Flexibility of Mind: The Role of
Mental Time Travel in Linguistic Comprehension and Production.” Philosophical Psychology 26
(2013): 24–46.
59. Dan P. McAdams, and Brad D. Olson. “Personality development: Continuity and change over the
life course.” Annual Review of Psychology 61 (2010): 517–42.
60. Robyn Fivush. “The Development of Autobiographical Memory.” Annual Review of Psychology
62 (2011): 559–82.
61. Pietro Perconti. “I limiti delle storie su se stessi.” In Prima e terza persona: Forme dell’identità e
declinazioni del conoscere. Edited by Fabrizio Desideri and Paolo Francesco Pieri. Bergamo:
Moretti & Vitali, 2013, pp. 45–56. (In Italian)
62. Gian Luca Barbieri. Tra testo e inconscio. Strategie della parola nella costruzione dell’identità.
Milano: Franco Angeli, 2007. (In Italian)
63. Katja Crone, Kristina Musholt, and Andrea Strasser. “Introduction: Towards an integrated theory
of self-consciousness.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 84 (2012): V–XVI.
64. This cluster is edited by Domenico Fiormonte and Michele Lucantoni. Mauro Bergonzi is author
of Section 6.2. We have summarized the original contribution of the late Emilio Del Giudice who
should be considered co-author of Section 6.1.
65. For reasons of space we have decided to leave Massimo Maraffa’s contribution out of this section.
However, we would like to thank him for his essential contribution that allowed us to include in
our original discussion the perspective on consciousness of western cognitive sciences.
66. Christof Koch. The Quest for Consciousness: A Neurobiological Approach. Englewood: Roberts
and Co. Publisher, 2004.
67. John Stewart Bell. “On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox.” Physics 1 (1964): 195–200.
68. Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky, and Nathan Rosen. “Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of
Physical Reality be Considered Complete?” Physical Review 47 (1935): 777–80.
Humanities 2014, 3
441
69. Niels Bohr. “Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?”
Physical Review 48 (1935): 696–702.
70. David Bohm. Quantum Theory. New York: Prentice Hall, 1951.
71. Benjamin Lee Whorf. Language, Thought and Reality. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1956.
72. George Berkeley. A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. 1710. University
of Oregon: Renascence Editions, 1999.
73. Nisargadatta Mahārāj. I Am That. Bombay: Chetana, 1973.
74. Max Planck. “Das Wesen der Materie”. Speech held in Florence, Italy, 1944. Archiv zur
Geschichte der Max-Planck-Gesellschaft, Abt. Va, Rep. 11 Planck, Nr. 1797, München,
Germany, 1944. (In German)
75. Erwin Schrödinger. What Is Life? with Mind and Matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1974.
76. George Spencer Brown. Laws of Form. New York: The Julian Press, 1972.
77. Gerald Edelman. Second Nature: Brain Science and Human Knowledge. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2006.
78. Juan Francisco Varela. “Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard
Problem.” Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (1996): 330–49.
79. Daniel Dennett. Consciousness Explained. New York: Back Bay Books, 1992.
80. Robert Nozick. Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World. London: Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press, 2001.
81. Amit Goswami. The Visionary Window: A Quantum Physicist’s Guide to Enlightenment.
Wheaton: Quest Books, 2006.
82. Hermann Röhrs. “The Classical Idea of the University. Its Origin and Significance as Conceived
by Humboldt.” In Tradition and Reform of the University under an International Perspective. Ed.
Hermann Röhrs. New York: Peter Lang, 1987, pp. 13–27. See also Thorsten Nybom. “The
Humboldt Legacy: Reflections on the Past, Present, and Future of the European University.”
Higher Education Policy 16 (2003): 141–59.
83. Mae-Wan Ho. “Illuminating Water and Life”. Entropy 16 (2014), in print.
© 2014 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article
distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license
(http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).