International Journal of Philosophical Studies
ISSN: 0967-2559 (Print) 1466-4542 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/riph20
Inheritance, Originality and the Will: Bergson and
Heidegger on Creation
Mark Sinclair
To cite this article: Mark Sinclair (2014) Inheritance, Originality and the Will: Bergson and
Heidegger on Creation, International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 22:5, 655-675, DOI:
10.1080/09672559.2014.913302
To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2014.913302
Published online: 01 Jul 2014.
Submit your article to this journal
Article views: 241
View related articles
View Crossmark data
Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=riph20
Download by: [Mark Sinclair]
Date: 11 May 2017, At: 03:23
International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2014
Vol. 22, No. 5, 655–675, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2014.913302
Inheritance, Originality and the Will:
Bergson and Heidegger on Creation
Mark Sinclair
Abstract
In the work of Henri Bergson and Martin Heidegger we find different responses
to traditional ideas of ‘creation’. Bergson advances a philosophy of creation,
wherein ‘creation’ is presented as the production of a ‘radical’ or ‘absolute’
novelty, not only in art, but in all forms of human experience and biological life.
Heidegger, in contrast, comes to criticise ideas of ‘creation’ in art as the expression of an alienated ‘humanism’ and ‘subjectivism’ essential to the modern age.
This paper illuminates this divergence by showing how Bergson and Heidegger,
despite appearances, grapple with the question of art-production – and with the
attendant issues of inheritance and originality – in similar ways. It is only in
recognising this proximity, I argue, that it is possible to perceive adequately what
essentially distinguishes their approaches: Bergson’s conception of creation as a
function of the will.
Keywords: Bergson; Heidegger; creation; genius; history; art
Henri Bergson and Martin Heidegger are two important twentieth-century philosophers who inherit traditional ideas of ‘creation’ in contrasting ways. From
at least his Creative Evolution of 1907, an idea of creation, developed according to the guiding thread of an interpretation of art production, becomes pivotal
in Bergson’s account of time as duration and in his philosophy as a whole. His
is a philosophy of creation, wherein ‘creation’ is presented as the production
of a ‘radical’ or ‘absolute’ novelty, not only in art, but in all forms of human
experience and biological life. In contrast, Heidegger comes to criticise ideas
of ‘creation’ in relation to art: such ideas, he argues, risk alienating us from
the historicity and essence of art, and are an expression of the ‘humanism’ and
‘subjectivism’ essential to the modern age. Bergson and Heidegger, then,
clearly differ on ‘creation’. In this paper, however, I argue that this difference
shelters a close – and hitherto unnoticed – proximity. The two philosophers
grapple in comparable ways with the question of ‘creation’ and with the attendant issues of inheritance and originality – and only in recognising that and
how they do so, I contend, is it possible to understand what ultimately separates them.1
© 2014 Taylor & Francis
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
The first section of the article offers an initial approach to an oft-misunderstood issue in Bergson’s work: his conception of creation is not univocal.
Despite his emphasis on ‘absolute’ or ‘radical’ novelty, ‘creation’, for Bergson,
is by no means necessarily antithetical to an idea of inheritance from nature
and history. It will become clear that Bergson and Heidegger share the project
of conceiving art production as something other than either mere reproduction
or production de novo – and that this leads both philosophers into a dialogue
with Aristotelian ideas. In a second section of the paper, I show that this
shared problematic is developed when both consider the role of history in art:
the doctrine of temporal retroactivity that Bergson advances in his later work
represents, I contend, the point at which he stands in the closest proximity to
the conception of temporality (Zeitlichkeit) and historicity (Geschichte) with
which Heidegger claimed to have surpassed his predecessor’s conception of
duration. And yet, at the very moment that Bergson affirms that creativity has
a retroactive effect on the past, he holds that the past has no bearing on the
present – and this according to a strong sense of ‘creation’ as the production
of absolute novelty. The final section of the essay will address not only the difficulties of this ‘creationist’ position but also unearth the grounds on which
Bergson adopts it: an idea of the will, and thus a philosophical voluntarism,
with which much of Bergson scholarship has still not come to terms.
1. Between Reproduction and Production de novo
It is first necessary to recall a fact long acknowledged but all too easily forgotten given our now vague and banalised ideas concerning ‘creativity’: the idea
of the human being as ‘creative’ has a theological background.2 In the Middle
Ages, and still in the early Renaissance, creatio and creare were seldom used
in relation to human acts and accomplishments, and the ability to produce
something ex nihilo – to create, properly speaking, rather simply to make –
was, in classical Augustinian terms, the prerogative of God.3 The move in the
Renaissance to describe artists as creators was, in fact, a revolutionary act of
an emergent humanism that, for many, would have been tantamount to blasphemy. The very idea of human creativity originally involves the idea of a
divine power to produce pure novelty, to produce something from nothing; and
even when human creativity is understood as merely analogous with divine
creativity, since the human artist ‘creates’ the form but not the pre-given matter
of the artwork, the idea of a miraculous and absolute power to produce novelty
still guides and underlies conceptions of human capabilities.4
In what sense does this theological background inform Bergson’s inheritance
of an idea of creation, an idea that he extends beyond art production to psychological and biological life as a whole? Bergson is certainly drawn to a conception of creation as the production of an absolute novelty, even if he cannot
admit creation ex nihilo given his argument that nothingness, like disorder and
656
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
like possibility, is an ens rationis posterior to sense-experience and which thus
contains not less but more than the idea of something. Bergson is certainly
drawn – to make the same point with different terms – to a conception of creation as radically de novo, as deriving from nothing (apart from the pre-given
work material) other than the present act of creation, and it can even be said
that this absolute sense of both creation and novelty guides his thinking as an
ideal from at least 1907. It is nevertheless the case that, as Newton Stallknecht
put it in 1934, ‘Bergson’s philosophy really contains two accounts of creation’:5 a conception of creation as the production of absolute novelty contrasts
with a more continuous conception of creation in Bergson’s work.
This can be elucidated with reference to a key footnote in the first chapter
of Creation Evolution, in which Bergson responds to Gabriel Séailles’ 1883
Essai sur le génie dans l’art. In this work Séailles attempts to think beyond
conceptions of genius as a principle discontinuous with nature and history. The
artist’s genius already resides in her selective appropriation of nature and history, he argues, and thus the difference between the product of genius and the
other products of life is a difference of degree rather than in kind. It is in this
sense that Séailles announces in the introduction that ‘[t]hought continues life,
it tends to assimilate to itself, to organise everything which enters into it’.
What Séailles says about thought applies to his account of genius: it is a principle continuous with life, insofar as it is a capacity to assimilate both history
and nature. Yet what was evidently of great interest to Bergson is Séailles’ further claim that what unites and underlies thought and life in their unity is a
‘creative principle (puissance créatrice)’;6 thought ‘can be defined, as much as
the life of the body, as “a creation”’.7 Thought, including the mode of
‘thought’ that is genius, is continuous with biological life, but life in its organisation is already a function of a ‘creative’ principle – and it clearly must be if
genius as a creative principle is not to be discontinuous with life itself. In
appealing thus to an idea of ‘creation’, however, Séailles is aware – the quotation marks already indicate this – of the extent to which he is deforming traditional usage, insofar as creation, on his account, involves assimilation and
precisely not production from nothing. As he acknowledges much later in the
book, genius, a principle continuous with life, is not, stricto sensu, creative;
genius ‘does not create, in the strict sense of the word; it does not produce
new forms from scratch (de toutes pièces)’.8 There is, then, a ‘creative’ principle underlying all the manifestations of life, but this creative principle cannot
be taken in any strict sense as the production of an absolute novelty.
Given that it clarifies one of the two ideas in the title of the book, the footnote in which Bergson responds to Séailles is perhaps the most important of
Creative Evolution as a whole.9 Within it, Bergson first seems to indicate that
Séailles remarks are a source of inspiration for his own attempts to locate a
creative principle in nature, but here is the footnote in its entirety:
657
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
In his beautiful book on Genius in Art, M. Séailles develops the double
thesis that art prolongs nature and that life is creation. We would happily
accept the latter formulation: but do we have to understand by ‘creation’,
as he does, a synthesis of elements? Wherever there are pre-existing
elements, the synthesis that will be made of them is given virtually
(virtuellement), being only one of the possible arrangements: and this
arrangement, amongst all the other possibilities that surrounded it, could
have been apprehended in advance by a superhuman intelligence. We
hold, on the contrary, that in the domain of life, the elements do not have
a real and separate existence. These are but successive views of the mind
on an indivisible process. And this is why there is radical contingency in
progress, an incommensurability between what proceeds and what
follows – that is, duration.10
Bergson does not explicitly comment on Séailles’ position that creation in this
context should not be understood in a strict or proper sense. Yet he implicitly
accepts this, and criticises only Séailles’ further claim that creation is a synthesis of separate ‘elements’. That creation is not ex nihilo or de novo does not,
Bergson holds, entail that it is synthetic or combinatorial in this way. Such an
approach, for Bergson, would reduce creation to mere making and fail to recognise the real extent to which there is novelty in the course of life. Presenting
an early expression of his arguments concerning the modal category of possibility, Bergson argues here that if the new thing is only an arrangement of
already separate elements then that thing was (in principle, and here in the
divine mind) foreseeable (and thus, as Bergson claims, ‘possible’ or ‘virtual’)
– but life in its progress and duration cannot be foreseen because it involves
radical contingency and incommensurability between past and future.11 The
present, as Bergson always argues, in no way determines what the future will
be. Unforeseeablility and indeterminism do not necessarily imply discontinuity,
however, and for this reason Bergson can use the term ‘element’ in a positive
sense: there are elements from which the new event emerges, but these do not
have a ‘real and separable existence’.
Bergson will develop this idea of production from ‘elements’ in Chapter II
of Creative Evolution in describing biological evolution, and this shows how
his account of biological life is influenced by his account of art production.12
Biological evolution, he writes, ‘never advances in the sense of an association,
but rather of dissociation, never towards convergence, but towards a divergence of effort’. Consequently, if there are ‘elements’ from which processes
and events emerge,
these are not comparable to objects juxtaposed in space, exclusive each
of the other, but rather to psychological states, of which each, though
itself to begin with, participates in the others and thus contains virtually
the whole of the personality to which it belongs.13
658
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
The singularity of forms of life and events emerges from an original interpenetrative unity. What is still more important for us, however, is that the footnote
referring to Séailles already makes clear that we should not take at face value
Bergson’s claims to a ‘radical’ and ‘absolute’ novelty. If creation did involve
an idea of absolute novelty or discontinuity, the very idea of a creative evolution would risk a contradiction in terms. Moreover, in 1907 Bergson treats creation as synonymous with maturation; after having stated that ‘the more we
dwell on the nature of time, the more we will understand that duration signifies
invention, creation of forms, continuous elaboration of the absolutely new’, he
can write of time as the ‘internal work of maturation or creation’.14 To note
this is not to deny that a second, discontinuous sense of creation emerges elsewhere in Bergson’s work. In The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, for
example, Bergson will return to the idea of a creative evolution by describing
‘the unforeseeability of forms that life creates from scratch (de toutes pièces),
by discontinuous leaps, all along its evolution’.15 What Séailles had denied,
that creation operates ‘from scratch’, Bergson affirms in 1930; and therefore he
seems to entertain the apparently contradictory idea of a discontinuous evolution. It nevertheless remains the case that in Creative Evolution Bergson
advances an idea of creation as irreducible both to reproduction and production
de novo, and that this idea of creation is involved in what he writes about
artistic inspiration as ‘aesthetic intuition’. Borrowing from Séailles, Bergson
holds that the artist attempts to capture the hidden ‘intention’ of her model,
thus placing herself in the ‘interiority of the object by a sort of sympathy’.16
As much as this sympathy brings something to the object, it nevertheless
draws something from its hidden interiority.
It is this conception of creation that can be compared productively with
Heidegger’s reflection on art production. Like Bergson, Heidegger seeks to
distinguish art production from traditional ideas of prosaic craft – and this is a
reason why, in the two early versions of ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’ delivered as lectures in 1935, there is no positive account of the former; we will
not, he argues, be able to account for the specificity of art production unless
we first determine what the artwork itself achieves or works in its reception.
Certainly, Heidegger’s approach may seem to contrast with Bergson’s emphasis
on novelty: art production is distinct from craft production, Heidegger holds,
not because it inherits less from what precedes it, but rather because it inherits
more. It is from this perspective that he thinks art with the verb schöpfen,
which according to the dictionary originally means to ‘draw from’, as ‘one
draws water from a well’.17 It nonetheless remains the case that when
Heidegger advances his interpretation of schöpfen in the final version of the
essay, he comes up against the question of the novelty of the original artwork
in a way such that his apparently different orientation by no means precludes
sharing common ground with Bergson.
This occurs within Heidegger’s attempt to overcome traditional conceptions
of matter according to his conception of Earth (Erde). The artist he argues,
659
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
does not simply impose from the outside a plan or blueprint on more or less
pliable, more or less recalcitrant materials, and, by working them up into a definite form, she does not simply act on them, forcing them to become what they
are not. Instead, the artist ‘draws from’ what we call her ‘materials’, and lets a
particular form come into presence. In art production there is an essential passivity, a ‘receiving and extracting (Entnehmen) within the relation to unconcealment (Unverborgenheit)’.18 In this context Heidegger retrieves Albrecht
Dürer’s dictum, according to which ‘in truth, art lies hidden within nature;
he who can wrest it from her, has it’.19 The dictum expresses what Erwin
Panofsky has described as a commonplace of Renaissance thinking, namely
the idea that the artwork is hidden in the work ‘material’ before it is unearthed
or extracted in the process of production – a process that is much more
‘revelatory’ than ‘creative’.20 And yet although Heidegger appropriates this
Renaissance commonplace by means of Dürer’s dictrum, he immediately
qualifies it. It is true that ‘hidden in nature’ is a ‘capacity for bringing forth
(Hervorbringenkönnen)’, and thus that art is hidden in nature, but ‘it is equally
certain that this art hidden in nature becomes manifest first through the work,
because it lies originally in the work’.21 Heidegger takes up the dictum, then,
because it offers a conception of art production as revelation rather than
creation, but he immediately qualifies the dictum, and thus its sense of revelation, in order to emphasise the originality and novelty of the artwork.
What is at stake here can be illuminated by returning to the ancient Greek
origin of this Renaissance conception of art-production: Aristotle’s notion of
dunamis, of power or potentiality. In Metaphysics Z we read: ‘energeia means
the presence – to huparchein – of the thing but not in the sense which we
mean by potentiality. We say that a thing is present potentially as Hermes is
present in the wood’.22 Since the wood is the statue potentially, the latter, as
Aristotle will note, needs only to be wrought out from the former by a process
of abstraction. This is to say that when Heidegger qualifies Dürer’s dictum, he
is engaging with an Aristotelian problematic concerning potentiality. More to
the point, he is responding to Aristotle’s question concerning the respective priority of actuality and potentiality. In Metaphysics Θ, Aristotle holds that actuality is ontologically prior to potentiality in that the finished product is more in
being, and thus higher than as yet unformed matter. He also acknowledges,
however, that actuality is prior to possibility epistemologically or conceptually
(to logo), since we cannot know what exactly the wood is capable of until we
experience whatever is produced from it.23 Heidegger, too, makes this epistemological point when he writes that the art hidden in nature becomes manifest
only by means of the work, and yet he seems to go further than this in claiming that the capacity is originally rooted ‘in the work’. I will return to this
problem in the following section, but Heidegger seems to say that these capacities are what they are only through the work, and in this case it is hard to see
how they can be pre-existing capacities at all.
660
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
Here, however, it is important to note that Aristotle’s conception of potentiality illuminates Bergson’s thinking also. It can, in fact, help us to think production in the sense intermediate between reproduction and production de novo
that Bergson intends. Certainly, it might be thought that Aristotle’s position is
antithetical to Bergson’s concern for novelty, for if the statue is already present
in the wood, then production would be tantamount to reduplication, and thus
nothing genuinely new would happen in the event. Yet Bergson’s critique of a
conception of possibility as conceivability and foreseeability has no bearing on
Aristotle’s notion of potentiality,24 for, as we have seen, Aristotle recognises
that our conceptions of what something can possibly or potentially be occur in
the event, after the fact. In addition, Aristotle says not that the statue is actually present before it is produced, but rather that it is potentially present, and
we can approach what he means by dunamis as a way of being, by recognising
that the passive power of the wood is what it is only in relation to the active
power of the carpenter to transform the wood. The finished product requires
the unification and fusion of different active and passive potentialities, potentialities that exist only in relation to each other. Hence the statue is clearly not
already, i.e., actually there in the wood; it is not actually, for that matter, anywhere at all. This is to say that Aristotle’s conception of potentiality no more
excludes a conception of novelty than Bergson’s own concern for the ‘elements’ from which a product derives. Of course, we might worry that
Aristotle’s dunamis is not sufficiently ‘dynamic’ or that his teleological essentialism excludes radical novelty – but these are, quite simply, different issues.
2. Retroactivity in History and Ecstatic Temporality
Both Bergson and Heidegger, then, attempt to think art production as something intermediate between reproduction and production de novo, and this
involves the recognition that originality is tied to inheritance – at least, as we
have seen, to inheritance from nature. Yet in his later work, and with his doctrine of retroactivity in history, Bergson develops this thought in ways that are
perhaps surprising. He argues not just that originality is tied to or bound by
inheritance, but that inheritance is a function of originality, and even ‘created’
by the latter; and this according to an absolute and genuinely radical
conception of creation that was not the primary sense of the term in Creative
Evolution.
Bergson articulates his doctrine of retroactivity in a 1920 lecture at The
University of Oxford that was reworked and published in French as ‘Le
possible et le réel’ in the 1934 La pensée et le mouvant. It is, however, in the
introduction to this volume that the doctrine receives its most deliberate
formulation, with an example that borrows from Emile Deschanel’s 1882 Le
romantisme des Classiques. We may well talk now of the romanticism of
Racine or Boileau, but:
661
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
the romantic aspect of classicism became manifest (ne s’est dégagé) only
by the retroactive effect of romanticism […]. If there had been no Rousseau, no Chateaubriand, no Vigny or Hugo, not only would we never
have noticed, but there would never really have been any romanticism in
the Classics of old, for this romanticism of the Classics is realised only
by the lifting-out (découpage), in their work, of a certain aspect (aspect),
and this aspect (la découpure), with its particular form, existed no more
in classical literature before the apparition of romanticism, than exists, in
a passing cloud, the amusing sketch that an artist perceives in it by
organising the amorphous mass according to his imagination. Romanticism operated retroactively on classicism, like the artist’s sketch on this
cloud. Retroactively it created its own prefiguration in the past, and an
explanation of itself by its antecedents.25
The idea that the romantic aspect of classicism was actually there all along,
but unnoticed, is, Bergson argues, merely a retrospective illusion – an illusion
ignorant of the way that the present can shape retroactively the past. The illusion is tenacious, and it is the fate of creative artists to be subjected to it, in
one way or another, by critics who discover, once the shock caused by the
novel work has receded, that the work was prefigured in the past. ‘Creative’
work is, to borrow the title of a recent book by Pierre Bayard, Le plagiat par
anticipation, and that is to say, anticipatory rather than actual plagiarism.26 It
involves repetition of the past – not the boring repetition of the same that
Bergson routinely opposes to creation, but rather repetition with a difference.
Yet if the new aspect of the past was not actually there all along, does that
mean that it was not there in any sense at all? There are two responses to this
question in Bergson’s later work, and these two responses are reducible to his
two senses of creation.
Bergson entertains an affirmative answer to the question in that he proposes
that the novelty of the present ‘could’ consist of ‘additions of new qualities,
created from scratch (de toutes pièces) and absolutely unforeseeable’.27 This is
no mere hypothesis given what he had claimed about creation ‘from scratch’
in The Two Sources of Morality and Religion. At the very moment, then, that
Bergson claims that the present has a retroactive effect on the past, he asserts
that the past has or, at least in particular instances, can have no bearing on the
present; the present can arise wholly de novo and the aspects that it ‘discovers’
would simply be imposed on the past by the present. Although Séailles had
resisted the idea of genius, the principle of ‘creation’, as arising de toutes
pièces, Bergson now affirms precisely that idea; and he does this in ‘The Possible and the Real’ and The Two Sources according to a rather more traditionally modern interpretation of ‘genius’ as a capacity for making absolute
beginnings. Moreover, he seems immediately to extend this conception of genial discontinuity in the history of art and literature into a conception of social
662
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
history more broadly understood. We may claim, he writes, to discover ‘premonitory signs’ of the modern advent of democracy in the periods preceding
it, but these are
in our eyes, signs only because we know the course, because the course
has been completed. Neither the course, nor its direction, nor in consequence, its end were given when these facts came into being: hence they
were not yet signs.28
Bergson sketches here a picture of history without tendencies, movements or
forces, and historical change seems to have become a matter of permanent revolution – and this not just as a desideratum.29 Certainly, Bergson admits in a
parenthesis that ‘not just any (non quelconque)’ novel reality is able to emerge
from a specific historical conjuncture, but what it is that prevents anything
being possible he does not say.
There is, however, another, negative answer to the question, and not just
because of the way Bergson obliquely qualifies his conception of social history. For the terms he uses to articulate the idea of retroactivity seem to presuppose that the new aspect was not imposed on, but drawn from the past. He
writes of ‘isolating (isoler)’ an aspect of the past, and uses a reflexive verb in
a passive sense, se dégager, and a noun, découpure, with privative prefixes to
describe what the present does to the past: the découpure or ‘cutting’ s’est
dégagé, was revealed in, or ‘lifted out of’ the past. Of course, if the aspect
was lifted out of the extant work of the past, it must in some sense have
already been there; perhaps not actually there, but at least, and as Aristotle put
it, potentially there. Moreover, if Bergson’s example of the artist’s imagination
amounts to a claim that the ‘amusing sketch’ is wholly other to the cloud that
occasioned it, then we would have to reject the idea that the cloud occasioned
the sketch at all – but Bergson obviously does not. It would also be difficult to
relate this to what he had said previously about artistic ‘inspiration’ as ‘aesthetic intuition’. Bergson certainly acknowledged late in his life that he never
presented a developed or complete aesthetic theory that he could call his
own,30 but if his example of the artist in the passage above is supposed to support a theory of art production ‘from scratch’, it would contrast sharply with
his previous position.
With this second response to the question, then, Bergson would affirm that
an aspect découpé in the tradition was somehow already there in that it was
drawn from or out of the past, and that this aspect did not previously exist.
Such a contradictory position may not seem to be the most auspicious basis
for philosophical thought. Yet precisely this contradiction is what Heidegger
also affirms in ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’ when describing aesthetic intuition as a ‘poetic projection’:
663
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
Poetic projection [dichtende Entwurf] comes from nothing in this respect,
that it never takes its gift from the ordinary and the traditional. Yet it
never comes from nothing in that what is projected by it is only the
withheld determination [Bestimmung] of historical [geschichtlichen]
Dasein itself.31
The original artwork comes from nothing that is already extant – and yet it does
not come from nothing, it does not emerge ex nihilo, in that it draws from the
past in order to be original. How, then, to make sense of such a contradiction?
Everything rests here on the sense of ‘history’ or Geschichte in Heidegger’s
hands. His claim that the work does in some sense arise ex historia is not to say
that the possibility of the original work in the present simply pre-existed the
present in the work of the past. Nor does it imply, conversely, that the possibilities of future work were ‘created’ in it by the retroactive effect of the original
work of art in the present. The point, for Heidegger, is that we do not have to
choose one of these options. Instead, we have to think both at the same time:
the original work reveals what the past made possible – but this possibility is
nothing without the original work in the present. It is therefore pointless to
wonder whether the possibility of the work chronologically precedes its actuality or vice versa: both appear at once and co-constitute the ‘shock of the new’.
We may claim that such an account of history was already implied in Kant’s
intriguing and elliptical remarks on canonical succession in §47 of the Critique
of Judgment.32 We may even argue that the ‘simultaneity’ of actuality and possibility in the sense described above is acknowledged by Aristotle, who in
Metaphysics Θ writes that ‘according to time, actuality is in one sense prior”
to potentiality “and in another sense not’.33 Yet Heidegger grounds his thinking
of potentiality and canonical succession in art on an idea of time or temporality
(Zeitlichkeit) as such.34 According to §68 of Being and Time (Sein und Zeit),
the past – and that is to say, the ‘having-been’ or ‘beenness (Gewesenheit)’ of
Dasein – can be taken up by means of ‘repetition (Wiederhölung)’ expressly as
a source of possibility for the future. Whether it be one’s own past or that of
world-history, ‘beenness’ is always a task. The past is not a realm of dead
necessity, and yet the possibilities it bequeaths are what they are only in their
repetition by means of the openness of the future. Accordingly, Heidegger
argues that what he terms ‘ecstatic temporality’ ‘does not mean a “succession”
(“Nacheinander”) of the ecstases. The future is not later than having-been, and
this is not earlier than the present’.35 Beenness is not a series of ‘nows’ that
are no longer, and the future is not a series of ‘nows’ that are not yet. Instead,
the past, the present and the future all ‘occur’, as it were, ‘at the same time’.
Hence as Heidegger writes in §6 of Being and Time, in advancing an idea that
is not foreign to Bergson’s thinking: ‘Dasein’s own past – and this always
means the past of its generation – is not something which follows along after
it, but something which already goes ahead of it’.36
664
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
Bergson does not deliberately advance any such conception of temporality,
and he does not transform or restate his account of duration to accommodate
his own idea of the retroactivity of the present on the past in history. Bergson,
in other words, does not show explicitly how the idea of retroactivity developed at the level of art history and ‘collective’ history impacts on his previous
accounts of duration and memory as experienced by each of us individually.
That he does not is one reason why his claims concerning retroactivity remain
merely promissory. Nevertheless, if there are ‘only a few indicators’ in
Bergson’s work concerning history and ‘historical duration’,37 as Jean Hyppolite noted in 1949, then these indicators point towards, I contend, a hermeneutic conception of history, and towards an ‘ecstatic’ idea of temporality that
would ground it. This is an important reason why it is not entirely fair that, as
Hyppolite also notes, ‘modern philosophies of temporalisation have criticised
Bergson for making nothing more of duration than “cohesion”, for not having
recognised the separations and the reunifications of the ecstasies of the past,
present and future’.38 According to such a critique, the account of duration that
Bergson establishes by criticising a linear and thus spatialised conception of
time is, in effect, a ‘negative chronology’ in that it says much more about what
duration or original time is not than about what ‘it is’.39 One might respond to
such a critique, following Hyppolite, by claiming that Bergson’s Matter and
Memory is already an attempt ‘to raise the problem’ of the separations and
reunifications of past, present and future and to ‘resolve’ it.40 Yet this response
passes over a fundamental point: even though he develops it only in relation to
social rather than personal history, Bergson’s conception of retroactivity clearly
goes beyond the idea of the past in-itself advanced in the text of 1896.41
3. Creation and the Will
According to the ‘ecstatic’ conception of time and history outlined above, it is
not simply the case that inheritance and originality are inextricably bound
together. Each is rather a function of the other; the artist can inherit from the
past to the degree that she is original, and she can be original to the degree
that she inherits. In one sense, Bergson expresses such a conception of inheritance and originality, and thus his thinking points towards a hermeneutic conception of time and history. Yet if the idea of inheritance and originality each
being a function of the other is not Bergson’s ‘official doctrine’ in his later
work – if, instead, he holds that the present retroacts on the past whilst drawing nothing from it – then it is necessary to determine both what is particular
to this doctrine, and what motivates him to adopt it.
One motivation seems to be that Bergson holds that novelty is, in itself, a
good thing. This becomes clear when, in the final paragraph of ‘The Possible
and the Real’, he illuminates the ethical import of his thinking. A doctrine of
creation and novelty can guide a way of life that is more joyful:
665
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
More joyful, because the reality that invents itself before our eyes will
give to each of us, continually, some of the satisfactions that art offers at
rare intervals for the privileged: it will reveal to us, beyond the fixity and
the monotony, which our senses, hypnotised by the constancy of our
needs, first see in it, the continual, endlessly repeating novelty, the original mobility (mouvante) of things.42
Now, if novelty is intrinsically a good thing, we can see why Bergson would
hold that we have access to an unadulterated form of it in our experience.
Almost two centuries before Bergson, however, Edmund Burke had insightfully rejected the idea that novelty is intrinsically good in the first section of A
Philosophical Enquiry into the Sublime and Beautiful. ‘Some degree of novelty’43 is certainly an ingredient of any experience of the beautiful and the sublime, but novelty is not, as Joseph Addison had held, an aesthetic category in
its own right, for it is not necessarily good; all kinds of novel things are, need
it be said, bad. Moreover, continual novelty would be, far from joyful, perfectly disconcerting. ‘The first and simplest emotion which we discover in the
human mind’, Burke argues, is ‘curiosity’, but ‘as those things which engage
us purely by their novelty, cannot attach us for any length of time, curiosity is
the most superficial of all the affections … and it always has an appearance of
giddiness, restlessness and anxiety’.44 There is, then, something infantile and
tiresome in what Bergson claims to be a matter purely of joy. A century after
Burke, Søren Kierkegaard puts the same point in an interrogative form: ‘Who
could want to be susceptible to every fleeting thing, the novel, which always
enervatingly diverts the soul anew?’45 Who, if not those who, strangely
enough, see no virtue in constancy?46 After Burke and Kierkegaard there is
nothing novel left for Heidegger to say about novelty in an epoch – die
Neuzeit, modernity or the time of the new – that defines itself by it. Yet after
analysing curiosity as a state of distraction in Being and Time, he does make
sure to state the obvious: the problem with the new is that it ‘is already fast
becoming passé’.47
There is another, more compelling motivation for Bergson’s positing of creation as the production of absolute novelty: his concern to elaborate and safeguard an idea of human freedom. Discontinuity between the past and present,
one might claim, allows for radical freedom, freedom to act wholly independently of the past. On this question of freedom, however, in the final paragraph
of ‘The Possible and the Real’, Bergson continues thus:
… we will, above all, be stronger, for we will feel ourselves participating, creators of ourselves, in the great work of creation, which is there
form the beginning and which continues before our eyes. Our capacity to
act, in grasping itself, will be intensified. Humiliated heretofore in at attitude of obedience, slaves of all kinds of natural necessities, we will lift
ourselves up, masters associated to a greater Master.48
666
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
A doctrine of radical novelty constitutes a ‘preparation for living well’49
because it will give us both joy and freedom, liberating us not only from boredom, but also from humiliation. Far from noble savages, we are originally
humiliated slaves; and consequently Bergson conceives freedom in terms of
intensification, strength and mastery, of self-mastery and mastery over nature.
The goal of modern philosophy, following Descartes, is mastery and possession of nature, and Bergson qualifies this only by adding that self-mastery in
the form of self-creation is also required. Certainly, the mastery of the subject
over nature can never be absolute, but we will nevertheless be able to associate
ourselves with the great work of creation that exceeds us, and which Bergson
seems – without further clarification – to describe as the ‘great Master’.
What is it, however, that enables us to create and thus create ourselves?
What allows us to lift ourselves up, to elevate ourselves above natural necessity? To lift oneself up requires effort, and where there is effort, there is will.
Creation, then, is a function of the will, and, if Bergson does not state this
explicitly in ‘The Possible and the Real’, he nevertheless affirms here that we
are artistic and creative when ‘we want to be (quand nous le voulons)’.50 Such
a voluntarist position may appear strange, particularly in the light of ordinary
intuitions about ‘creativity’ containing an essential element of inspiration irreducible to perspiration. One wonders how such a voluntarist position could
make sense of, say, ‘writer’s block’ or the ‘difficult second album’. The position is all the more strange in that within Kant’s third Critique, the locus classicus of the modern concept of genius, the principle of fine art production is
independent of the will.51 Yet Bergson’s remark is not inadvertent, since in
Creative Evolution, he had already claimed that ‘the principle of all life’, and
thus all duration, is ‘a pure willing (un pur vouloir)’.52 Certainly, if as Bergson
writes in ‘Dreams’, ‘waking and willing (veiller et vouloir) are one and the
same’,53 he might have considered creation, like dreaming, to be a form of
relaxation or even negation of the will. Yet he does not, and the reason why
not is, in the end, patent: if life is creation, and if life is will, then creation
itself cannot be anything but voluntary. Bergson evidently wants to hold on to
the thought that life is creation, and to develop the idea that life is a function
of the will; but given that his idea of creation in developed according to the
guiding thread of reflection on art production, this leads to a voluntarist conception of the latter, and of what, for him, is its principle, namely genius. In
fact, in The Two Sources of Morality and Religion Bergson explicitly speaks of
genius as a function of the will. There exist ‘volontés géniales’, genial acts of
will, volitions that are at once acts of genius; ‘the will has its genius’, Bergson
holds, ‘as does thought, and genius defies all prevision’.54 What exactly
Bergson could mean here with the idea that the will is in possession of genius
is open to question, but genius would not be a force or faculty external to the
will, but rather one internal to it.
Within an important recent study, Arnaud François remarks that Bergson’s
theory of the will has ‘little drawn the attention of commentators’, principally
667
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
because it is most explicitly developed in lectures, rather than in the works
published in his lifetime.55 François shows how Bergson’s reflection on the
will begins with an idea of the unity of memory and future-oriented, voluntary
action as a function of a variable ‘vital tone’ or ‘tension’, which is independent
of, though related to, the will; and how this position later develops into the
more radical claim that the essence of all consciousness, and thus all life and
duration, is will.56 It is this emergent voluntarism, I contend, that forms the
background to, and provides a motivation for, Bergson’s positing of discontinuity. For, given the apparently brute and unmovable fact of the past, the purest
expression of the will – at least if one does not follow Nietzsche’s thought of
the Eternal Return of the Same – would be an entirely self-grounding, purely
voluntary principle of creativity entirely independent of the past. That such a
conception of discontinuity returns us to the cinematic conception of movement and time that Bergson so effectively criticised in 1907 would be merely
an inconvenience for a philosopher able to sacrifice, as we have seen, a rich
and viable account of artistic production and aesthetic intuition for, in the end,
the sake of the will. In any event, the consequences of such radical voluntarism can easily be drawn: if all creation is a pure willing, and if all creation is
necessarily a self-creation, then all creation is ultimately a ‘will to will’ – a
willing that intends, through its ‘creative expressions’, to augment its own
power and mastery.
‘Modern subjectivism’, as Heidegger remarks in ‘The Origin of the Work of
Art’, ‘immediately misinterprets creation as the sovereign subject’s performance of genius (mißdeutet freilich das Schöpferische sogleich im Sinne der
genialen Leistung des selbstherrlichen Subjektes)’.57 The remark points to a
simple fact, namely that the idea of genius as the principle of fine art production arises in the eighteenth century, and belongs to the epoch of modern philosophy that Heidegger terms the ‘modern metaphysics of subjectivity’. To be
sure, the remark is vague and risks interpretative violence if it were supposed
to apply, for example, to the Critique of Judgment. Not only can genius not be
reduced to the will and sovereignty in Kant’s analysis, but the latter contains
echoes of an inspiration theory of art production as distinct from a creation
theory; genius can act as a conduit for nature, as Kant suggests in §46, whilst
§47, as noted above, presents genius as intrinsically bound to history and
inheritance, albeit in a way that Kant admits he is not quite able to comprehend.58 In a lecture course of 1944, however, it becomes clear that the most
immediate target of this remark was not Kant, but Nietzsche, in whose conception of the will to power, as Heidegger argues, the ‘modern thought of the
human as “genius” expresses itself with its final consequence’. Heidegger continues as follows:
The thought of the creative human, or, stated more clearly, the thought
that the human achieves its highest fulfilment in creativity and as genius
… is founded on the modern determination of the essence of the human
668
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
as subject setting-itself-upon itself [als des sich-auf-sich-selbst stellenden
Subjektes], by which all ‘objects’ are first determined as such in their
objectivity. By setting its essence upon itself, the human rises into the
willing of its self. With this up-rising [Aufstand] of the human into the
will as the willing of itself, all things simultaneously become an object
for the first time.59
Here Heidegger uses schöpfen to speak of creation in a sense he aims to delimit,
rather than trying to draw on the original sense of the German word to advance
an inspiration or revelation theory that would contrast, strico sensu, with a creation theory. In any case, his first point is that the idea of the human being as
possessing a creative power, a power to produce absolute novelty, is an expression of the basic metaphysical position of an a-historical, supra-natural and thus
self-grounding subject – a basic position that was prepared for, as Heidegger
goes on to note, in the Renaissance. Yet this fundamental metaphysical position
already contains, as Heidegger seems to assert, the idea of the primacy of the
will that will clearly emerge, in various ways, later in the course of modern
philosophy: the primacy of the will is what the idea of sovereignty and
self-grounding already contains. Hence it should come as no real surprise that
creation and genius appear later in Nietzsche’s work explicitly as a function of
will, for this is simply what the idea of self-grounding, which underlies the idea
of human creativity, presupposes.
Heidegger offers these remarks about creation and genius towards the end of
a long trajectory of thinking on the question of the will – which, at the beginning of the 1930s, had included an explicit philosophical voluntarism that, as
recent scholarship has underlined, partially motivated his disastrous political
interventions in the Third Reich.60 It is not possible to trace this trajectory
here, and our concern lies simply with the fact that the ‘thought of the human
as creative and as genius’ expresses itself with this ‘final consequence’ in
Bergson, as well as in Nietzsche. Certainly, in one sense – the improper sense
– Bergson’s doctrine of creation does not attain this final consequence, in that
it does not exclude, as we have seen, revelation of history and nature in the
production of ‘novelty’. The concept of aesthetic intuition in relation to nature
that Bergson inherits from Ravaisson and Séailles is close to Heidegger’s at
once Aristotelian and post-modern conception of art production, as is the less
‘official’ aspect of Bergson’s doctrine of retroactivity in history. Yet, in
another, proper and absolute sense, one that Bergson expresses in his later
work, creation becomes solely a function of the self-grounding voluntary subject, master of itself and the objects arrayed before it. To be sure, we might
wonder whether the will is much more of a cosmic than an individual principle
in Bergson’s work – but it is Bergson who says we are artistic when we want
to be, and even if it were an impersonal principle, genius, as a function of the
will and as a principle of discontinuous radical novelty, would still amount to
669
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
alienation from history and nature. Of course, one might also claim that the
virtue of Bergson’s evolutionary theory is precisely to challenge modern
humanism and ‘subjectivism’, and this, in particular, by extending a sense of
creativity to the non-human, to biological life as a whole. Yet as Bergson’s
final remarks in ‘The Possible and the Real’ make plain, extending a fundamentally modern metaphysical position concerning genius, creativity and the
will beyond human life does not amount to a transformation of that position.
To read Bergson, I conclude, is to be confronted with the necessity of a
decision. This is not, to be sure, the decision: Bergson or Heidegger. Yet nor is
it simply the oft-discussed decision between Bergson as a thinker of either continuity or discontinuity. Certainly, Bergson does posit creative discontinuity –
at least as an ideal – but now we can recognise what this discontinuity
involves: mastery, domination, will, and ultimately the will to will. In this
light, it is plain to see that the problem of Bergson’s conception of discontinuous, radical novelty is not that it reintroduces an idea of transcendence into
duration, precisely where we might least want it; the problem is rather that it is
all too immanent, for it cannot see any other activity in art-production than that
of a self-grounding, self-sufficient subject. In opposition to discontinuity in this
sense, however, Bergson does more than simply propose an idea of continuity,
particularly in that the doctrine of retroactivity leads him to the idea that our
freedom and futurity is produced by, and not just limited or conditioned by,
the past – and vice versa. The decision, then, is this: between, on the one
hand, a fulfilment of the modern metaphysics of subjectivity, and, on the other
hand, a recognition that originality and inheritance are a function of each other,
and that both are irreducible to the will. It is in the light of this decision that
we will be able to judge adequately more recent philosophies of creation, and
even of creation ex nihilo, in contemporary French thinking.
Manchester Metropolitan University, UK
Notes
1 Attempts to relate Bergson and Heidegger’s thinking have begun to emerge in
recent scholarship: see, in particular, Heath Massey, ‘On the Verge of Being and
Time: Before Heidegger’s Dismissal of Bergson’, Philosophy Today 54(2) (2010),
pp. 138–56.
2 For a longer treatment of this issue see Nahm, ‘The Theological Background to the
Theory of the Artist as Creator’, Journal of the History of Ideas 8(3) (1947),
pp. 362–72.
3 On this particular point, see Edgar Zilsel, Die Entstehung des Geniebegriffs – Ein
Beitrag zur Ideengeschichte der Antike und des Frühkapitalismus (Hildesheim/New
York: Olm, 1972), p. 225.
4 See Nahm, ‘The Theological Background’, p. 366.
5 Newton Stallknecht Studies in the Philosophy of Creation with Especial Reference
to Bergson and Whitehead (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1934), p. 53.
670
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
6 Gabriel Séailles, Essai sur le génie dans l’art (Paris: Librairie Germer Baillière,
1883), p. ix. All translations from this text are my own.
7 Ibid., p. viii.
8 Ibid., p. 154.
9 The importance of Séailles’ book for Bergson’s project in 1907 is seldom acknowledged, but for an exception see Ansell-Pearson, ‘Bergson’s Encounter with Biology’, Angelaki 10(2) (2005), pp. 59–72.
10 Bergson, Œuvres (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1959), pp. 518–19; Creative Evolution, trans. A. Mitchell (New York, H. Holt, 1913), p. 30.
11 Like the idea of creation, ‘virtuel’ is another term that Bergson uses in two senses
that are difficult to dissociate merely by reference to the chronology of his writings.
In the passage cited it is a synonym of an intellectualist conception of the possible
as conceivability – and Bergson treats the terms as synonymous whenever he criticises the modal category of possibility. Yet, he also uses the term in a more positive
sense that develops traditional ideas of potentiality. In this sense John Mullarkey is
right to remark that ‘no clear water exists in Bergson’s texts between the virtual and
the possible as it does in Deleuze’s reading’: Mullarkey, ‘Forget the Virtual:
Bergson, Actualism and the Refraction of Reality’, Continental Philosophy Review
37(2) (2004), pp. 469–93, p. 492.
12 That Bergson interprets natural process and production through the lens of artistic
production is still more obvious in the French neologism génialité that Bergson
coins to describe the movement of biological life: Œuvres, p. 624. When Arthur
Mitchell translated this term as ‘fervour’ he obscured its derivation from an idea of
genius as the principle of art production; Creative Evolution, p. 173. Certainly, that
natural process is interpreted through the lens of art does not preclude the possibility that there are significant differences in the sense of creation across these
‘domains’ – but Bergson seems more concerned to underline the similarities rather
than the differences between them.
13 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 595; Creative Evolution, pp. 125–126.
14 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 503; Creative Evolution, pp. 11–12. This is a particularly acute
example of the two different senses of ‘creation’ in Bergson’s work, and of his
tendency to elide them.
15 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1072; The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, trans. R. Audra
Ashley and C. Brereton (Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1977), p. 95.
16 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 645; Creative Evolution, p. 187.
17 Martin Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, Gesamtausgabe Vol. 5:
Holswege (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1995), p. 63; ‘The Origin of the Work
of Art’, in Off the Beaten Track, trans. K. Haynes and J. Young (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press), p. 48.
18 Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, p. 50; ‘The Origin of the Work of
Art’, p. 37.
19 Cited in Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, p. 58; ‘The Origin of the
Work of Art’, p. 43.
20 See Panofsky, Idea, trans. J. Peake (New York: Harper Collins, 1975). Robert
Bernasconi (‘Ne sutor ultra crepidam: Erasmus and Dürer at the hands of Panofsky
and Heidegger’, in Heidegger and the Art of Existing [New York: Humanities Press,
1993], pp. 118–34) has suggested that Heidegger takes Dürer’s dictum out of
context, and that it is concerned only with the question of fidelity to nature in the
artistic imitation of its forms. Yet this claim loses much of its force when we consider that Heidegger is retrieving a Renaissance commonplace of which Dürer was
undoubtedly aware.
671
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
21 Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, p. 58; ‘The Origin of the Work of
Art’, p. 43.
22 Aristotle, Metaphysics Z, 1048a 32-3.
23 See Aristotle, Metaphysics Θ 1049b13.
24 On this point, see Jean-Louis Chedin, ‘Deux Conceptions du Possible: Aristote et
Bergson’, La revue de l’enseignement philosophique 37(2) (1986), pp. 36–50.
25 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1264; The Creative Mind, trans. M. Andison (New York:
Philosophical Library, 1946), pp. 23–24.
26 See Pierre Bayard, Le plagiat par anticipation (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 2009).
27 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1264; The Creative Mind, p. 23.
28 Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1264; The Creative Mind, p. 24.
29 Henri Davenson (‘Bergson et l’histoire’, in Henri Bergson : Essais et témoignages
recueillis, ed. A. Béguin and P. Thévenaz [Neuchatel: Editions de la Baconnière,
1943], p. 207) counters claims that Bergson is an anti-historical thinker by pointing
out that his accounts of duration and retroactivity allow ‘the historian to flourish
and liberate himself’ (p. 207, translation mine) from the idea that history is a matter
of recording chronological facts settled once and for all. This response, however,
does not address the issue of the meaning and possibility of historical action and
the movement of history itself – of Geschichte, to use the terms that Davenson borrows from Heidegger, rather than Historie, as the study of history.
30 See Isaac Benrubi, ‘Un entretien avec Bergson’, in Henri Bergson: Essais et
témoignages recueillis, ed. A. Béguin and P. Thévenaz (Neuchatel: Editions de la
Baconnière, 1943), p. 368.
31 Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, pp. 63–64; ‘The Origin of the Work
of Art’, p. 49.
32 For the claim that Kant’s remarks on exemplarity and canonical succession in The
Critique of Judgment imply a ‘hermeneutic’ understanding of history see Jay
Bernstein, The Fate of Art (London: Polity, 1992), pp. 99–101. The further claim
that Heidegger’s thinking of history is ‘modelled’ on Kant’s brief and elliptical
remarks, risks succumbing to the retrospective illusion that Bergson diagnoses.
33 Metaphysics IX, viii, 1049b12. On the basis of this text, and in concluding an
extended argument that it is not possible to rehearse here, Pierre Aubenque (Le
problème de l’être chez Aristote [Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1966],
pp. 442–3; my translation) argues that: ‘the debate concerning the respective priority
of possibility and actuality is a false debate. Actuality and possibility are co-originary; they are only the ecstasies of movement; only the clash of possibility and
actuality at the heart of movement is real; only the violence of human discourse
[…] can maintain dissociated […] the originary tension which constitutes, in its
unity that is ever divided, the being of the being in movement.’
34 It is not possible here to engage with the problem of Heidegger’s move – if it is
one – from individual temporality to ‘collective’ history in Being and Time.
35 Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tübingen: Max Niemeyer, 1984), p. 350.
36 Ibid., p. 20.
37 Jean Hyppolite, ‘Various Aspects of Memory in Bergson’, trans. A. V. Coleman, in
Leonard Lawlor, The Challenge of Bergsonism (London: Continuum 2003),
pp. 112–28, p. 114.
38 Ibid., p. 113.
39 For the germs of such critique, see Heidegger, Being and Time, p. 432.
40 Hyppolite, ‘Various Aspects of Memory in Bergson’, p. 114.
41 This is one reason why we should not be surprised that there is no mention of
Matter and Memory (MM) in any of Bergson’s discussions of retroactivity. There
is, however, at least one more reason: Bergson develops the thought of retroactivity
672
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
in relation to the history of art and then social history, which is very different from
the paradigm of personal memory in MM, according to which we have to have
experienced a past event in person for it to be able to reappear in the horizon of the
present (in perception, explicit recollection, dreams, etc.). The present-day genius
has not experienced, say, ancient Greece in person, and yet through her that epoch
can present itself in a new way. Craig Lundy (‘Bergson, History and Ontology’ in
Bergson and the Art of Immanence: Painting, Photography, Film, eds. J. Mullarkey
and C. de Mille [Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2013], pp. 17–31) has
recently attempted to defend Bergson against the claim that there is no philosophy
of history to be found in his work, but for the reason I have just adduced it is from
the account of retroactivity rather than from Matter and Memory that we might be
able to draw one.
Bergson, Œuvres, pp. 1344–5; The Creative Mind, p. 105. On a political or social
level Bergson wonders to what extent change can be recommended (Œuvres,
p. 1328; The Creative Mind, p. 88), but here on a personal level he seems to see no
problem in recommending that we apprehend it.
Edmund Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the
Sublime and the Beautiful, ed. A. Phillips (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990),
p. 29.
Ibid.
Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling/Repetition, ed. E. Hong and H. Hong (New
Jersey: Princeton, 1983), p. 133.
Bergson can see some virtue in constancy, but only insofar as it provides a basis for
novelty, which is irreducible to, less boring and thus better than it: ‘there will be
novelty in our acts only thanks to what we have found to be of a repetitive nature
in things’: Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1334; The Creative Mind, p. 94.
Martin Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe Bd. 65: Beiträge zur Philosophie: (Vom Ereignis) (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1989), p. 55; Contributions to Philosophy
(On the Event), trans. R. Rocjewicz and D. Vallega-Neu (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2012), p. 45.
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1345; The Creative Mind, pp. 105–6.
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1345; The Creative Mind, p. 106.
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1334; The Creative Mind, pp. 93–4.
See Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. N. Walker (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2007), p. 137: ‘where an author owes a product to his genius, he does not himself
know how the ideas for it have entered into his head, nor has he it in his power to
invent the like at pleasure.’
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 697; Creative Evolution, p. 251. In the recent critical edition
of La pensée et le mouvant (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2009; p. 385)
Arnaud Bouaniche notes that this remark is not inadvertent, but without drawing
out its philosophical consequences.
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 893; Mind-energy: Lectures and Essays, trans. H. Wildon Carr
(Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1975), p. 127.
Bergson, Œuvres, p. 1023; The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, trans. R. Audra
Ashley and C. Brereton (Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977), p. 44.
Arnaud François, Bergson, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche: volonté et réalité (Paris:
Presses Universitaires de France, 2008), p. 48.
See Ibid., pp. 48–71.
Heidegger, ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, p. 64; ‘The Origin of the Work of
Art’, p. 52.
See Bernstein, The Fate of Art, pp. 99–100, for a reading of Kant’s analysis of genius that takes up these points against Heidegger’s remark.
673
INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES
59 Heidegger, Gesamtausgabe Bd. 50: Einleitung in die Philosophie: Denken und
Dichten (Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann, 1990), pp. 110–11; Introduction
to Philosophy: Thinking and Poetizing, trans. P. Braunstein (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2011), p. 20.
60 See Bret Davis, Heidegger and the Will: On the Way to Gelassenheit (Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 2007), and, for an opposing view, Vincent Blok,
‘“Massive Voluntarism” or Heidegger’s Confrontation with the Will’, Studia
Phenomenologica 13 (2013), 449–65.
References
Ansell-Pearson, K. (2005) ‘Bergson’s Encounter with Biology: Thinking Life’, Angelaki
10(2): 59–72.
Aubenque, P. (1966) Le problème de l’être chez Aristote, Paris: Presses Universitaires
de France.
Bayard, P. (2009) Le Plagiat par anticipation, Paris: Editions de Minuit.
Benrubi, I. (1942) ‘Un entretien avec Bergson (Fragment de journal)’, in A. Béguin and
P. Thévenaz (eds) Henri Bergson: Essais et témoignages recueillis, Neuchatel:
Editions de la Baconnière.
Bergson, H. (1913) Creative Evolution, trans. A. Mitchell, New York, NY: H. Holt & Co.
———. (1946) The Creative Mind, trans. M. Andison, New York, NY: Philosophical
Library.
———. (1959) Œuvres, Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
———. (1975) Mind-energy: Lectures and Essays, trans. H. Wildon Carr, Westport,
CT: Greenwood Press.
———. (1977) The Two Sources of Morality and Religion, trans. R. Audra Ashley and
C. Brereton, Indiana, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
———. (2009) La pensée et le mouvant, ed. F. Worms, Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France.
Bernasconi, R. (1993) ‘Ne sutor ultra crepidam: Erasmus and Dürer at the hands of
Panofsky and Heidegger’, in Heidegger and The Art of Existing, New York, NY:
Humanities Press: 118–34.
Bernstein, J. (1992) The Fate of Art, London: Polity.
Blok, V. (2013) ‘“Massive Voluntarism” or Heidegger’s Confrontation with the Will’,
Studia Phaenomenologica 13: 449–65.
Bouaniche, A. (1959) ’Le possible et le réel’, in H. Bergson, Œuvres, Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Burke, E. (1990) A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime
and the Beautiful, ed. A. Phillips, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chedin, J.-L. (1986) ‘Deux conceptions du possible: Aristote et Bergson’, La revue de
l’enseignement philosophique 37(2): 36–50.
Davenson, H. (1943) ‘Bergson et l’histoire’, in A. Béguin and P. Thévenaz (eds) Henri
Bergson: Essais et témoignages recueillis, Neuchatel: Editions de la Baconnière, pp.
205–13.
Davis, B. (2007) Heidegger and the Will: On the Way to Gelassenheit, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Deschanel, E. (1882) Le romantisme des Classiques, Paris: Calmann-Lévy.
François, A. (2008) Bergson, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche: volonté et réalité, Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Heidegger, M. (1984) Sein und Zeit, Tübingen: Verlag.
674
INHERITANCE, ORIGINALITY AND THE WILL
———. (1989) Gesamtausgabe Bd. 65: Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis),
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
———. (1990) Gesamtausgabe Bd. 50: Einleitung in die Philosophie: Denken und
Dichten, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.
———. (1995) ‘Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes’, in Gesamtausgabe Bd. 5: Holzwege,
Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
———. (2002) ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’, in Off the Beaten Track, trans.
K. Haynes and J. Young, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1–56.
———. (2011) Introduction to Philosophy: Thinking and Poetizing, trans.
P. Braunstein, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Heidegger, M. (2012) Contributions to Philosophy (On the Event), trans. R. Rocjewicz
and D. Vallega-Neu, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Hyppolite, J. (2004) ‘Various Aspects of Memory in Bergson’, trans. A.V. Coleman in
Leonard Lawlor, The Challenge of Bergsonism, London: Continuum: pp. 112–28.
Kant, I. (2007) Critique of Judgment, trans. N. Walker, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Kierkegaard, S. (1983) Fear and Trembling/Repetition, ed. E. Hong and H. Hong, New
Jersey: Princeton.
Lundy, C. (2103) ‘Bergson, History and Ontology’, in J. Mullarkey and C. de Mille
(eds) Bergson and the Art of Immanence: Painting, Photography, Film, Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, pp. 17–31.
Massey, H. (2010) ‘On the Verge of Being and Time: Before Heidegger’s Dismissal of
Bergson’, Philosophy Today 54(2): 138–56.
Mullarkey, J. (2004) ‘Forget the Virtual: Bergson, Actualism and the Refraction of
Reality’, Continental Philosophy Review 37(2): 469–93.
Nahm, M. (1947) ‘The Theological Background of the Theory of the Artist as Creator’,
Journal of the History of Ideas 8(3): 362–72.
Panofsky, E. (1975) Idea, trans. J. Peake, New York, NY: Harper Collins.
Séailles, G. (1883) Essai sur le génie dans l’art, Paris: Librairie Germer Baillière.
Stallknecht, N. (1934) Studies in the Philosophy of Creation with Especial Reference to
Bergson and Whitehead, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Zilsel, E. (1972) Die Entstehung des Geniebegriffs – Ein Beitrag zur Ideengeschichte
der Antike und des Frühkapitalismus, Hildesheim/New York, NY: Olm, 1972.
675