Bill of Rights for Australia: - Is It Necessary?
Ricky Gordon
Edith Cowan University
POL2127 – Australian Politics
When it comes to the issue of Bill of rights in Australia perhaps the question is not on why
there is none, but rather on whether there is a need for one. A mention of the bill of rights out
rightly leads most people to think of the first, second and fifth amendments that gave people the
freedom of speech, protection on gun ownership and the right to remain silent for suspects as
outlined in the American Constitution. The truth, however, is that Australia just like America, has
a constitution that goes way back to the founders and which are extremely hard to amend.
Australia is one of the oldest democracies which up to date has not adopted the bill of rights. As
such, policy makers are at crossroads when it comes to enacting the bill of rights. Some
legislatures think that the bill of rights will be effective in promoting the liberties of people,
religious tolerance and offer equal opportunities to every group. Further, they argue that
Australians need the bill of rights due to the inadequacies evident in the constitutional provisions
and several constitutional clauses have a narrow scope, exhibiting difficulties in interpretation.
However, concerns arise as the bill of rights contains uncertainties that are unavoidable and fails
to take into account the countervailing aspects such as racial vilification and defamation. The bill
of rights is not effective in guaranteeing i di iduals full protection of freedom and liberty rights.
The freedoms in the bill of rights denote to be illusionary, and it oppresses the citizens. The judges
enforce the laws enacted by the parliament, and hence the citizens are able to enjoy the freedom
of liberties. The parliament is where the will of people can be expressed using the ballot box. The
bill of rights is only grounded on the idea that the people's rights are conferred upon by the
judiciary system. The principles and values of Australians are reflected in the parliamentary elect,
and thus democracy is entrenched in the constitutional rights.
The bill of rights is unnecessary.
The Australian Human Rights Centre (AHRC) defines human rights as the interdependence
of civil, economic, political and social rights (Williams, 2017). In a system of government created
by the founders of Australia, what proceeds, is a constitution and legal system that incorporates
all of these factors regarding the rights of its citizenship already. Some of the human rights
provisions that can be found in the constitution include: Section 41, gives the right to vote,
section 51, protection against acquisition of property illegally and section 116, freedom of
worship (Nadim, 2015). An effective way of addressing political power is through dividing it
(checks and balances principle) and the use of the federal constitution ensures that there is the
correct division of power in all practices. Muhlenberg (2005) views Australia as already a nation
with strong foundations and safeguards of human rights through the maintained checks and
balances system which provides security to the citizens more effectively than the Bill of rights
could. With the bill placing emphasis on the justice system, its effectiveness could be limited
especially in Australia where a dynamic social-political context exists. It is critical to note that the
performance of the judiciary is entangled in the debate of what is true in the political setting.
The bill of rights can reduce the Individual rights of citizens.
Religious, economic and political freedoms exist in cases where freedom and liberty of
individuals prevail (Kant, 1929). Traditionally, the purpose behind the doctrine of human rights
has been to protect individuals from dominance by groups (Chandra, 2017). A bill of rights poses
a threat to individual human rights because the interests of the group are given primacy over the
rights of the individual (Newton, Thannhauser, & Jackman, 1998). This is clearly seen in the case
of cults in the US, due to the broad definition of the right to freedom of religion. To specify, the
right to freedo
of religio , does t prote t people agai st u ethi al oer io pro esses that
are applied i religious ults (Pretorius, 2018, p. 220). The Schuppin v. Unification Church case
exemplifies this, where the plaintiff was forced to work in compulsory service. The lawsuit fell
short due to the plaintiff proving that the use of mental restraint to retain the member in the cult
was used but not physical force, demonstrating that the rights of the individual were
overshadowed by the legal requirements of the bill at the hands of the group (Lucksted & Martell,
1982). Pretorius goes on to highlight that what can be discerned from these rulings is that
protection of the right to freedom of religion does not cover every act that may result on the
grou ds of a
e
er s i terpretatio of his or her parti ular elief s ste . (2018, p. 227).
Furthermore, In society there is often a divergence between interests and wants of individuals
and what is desirable for the welfare and safety of the group (Pecorino, 2001). If a bill were to be
enacted, the judiciary, rather than the government is faced with what Huscroft, Miller, and
Webber (2014) all opti isi g o eptio s of proportio alit ; here the gai i pu li i terest
is weighed against the restriction placed on the right using the principal of proportionality. When
addressing the balance of competing interests, the problem (as clarified in the next paragraph)
becomes that the judiciary is not able to provide objectively justifiable conclusions compared to
the democratically justifiable conclusions of the legislature (Huscroft, Miller, & Webber, 2014).
Therefore, the principal behind the doctrine of human rights is challenged under a bill of rights
and the enactment of the bill perverts its original intention.
The bill of rights will weaken the democracy of the nation.
The bill of the rights will profoundly weaken the democracy of Australia due to the cost of
judi ial di tatorship. Charles orth, a propo e t of e a ti g the ill of rights argues that a ri her
understanding of democracy, involves acknowledging that there are some rights that are so basic
to human dignity, that they should be taken out of the political arena and given special
prote tio
(2002, p. 39). The halle ge
ith Charles orth s ie
is the fa t it ig ores
hat
Waldron (1999) would consider to be the judiciary cost imposed on democracy. This cost is a
result of the judiciary review process, which is incurred on democratic society following judges
decisions regarding human rights matters. This occurs because judges can be driven by various
political and ideological affiliations, et are t e posed to the sa e de o rati for es that
elected representatives are. In other words, politicians are elected and it is in their interest to
adhere to majority sentiment if they wish to maintain power. Judges do not have this framework
to consider when making decisions. Furthermore, according to Waldron, considerations
regardi g
hat rights people should ha e is si pl
o s ie tious i i dis ussio
ithout a
deadli e (1993, p. 35), inferring that rights are not simply cost-benefit calculations but are
evolving philosophical debates amongst society concerning morality. Thus, elected members are
voted in by society which invalidates the power of the judiciary to promote democracy (Hitchens,
2003). The enactment of the bill can lead to judicial dictatorship that would affect the rule of law,
eroding democracy in Australia.
judicial review always incurs some kind of democratic cost because the decision has
been made by non-democratic means. If a court makes a good decision about a
democratic right, there is some substantive gain for democracy to set off against that
loss. Where a court makes a bad decision, however, then there is both a substantive
and a procedural cost for democracy (Stone, 2002, p. 487).
Excessive power and politicisation of the judiciary.
The bill of rights diminishes parliamentary supremacy which politicises and emboldens the
judiciary with excessive power. People have argued that the dynamics between security and
rights is rather one-sided under the current system, and with the enactment of a bill of rights,
ethical judicial decision-making would be substituted for political negotiation (Mason, 2006). On
the other side, others argue that advocates of the bill of rights neglect the flaws of a courtcentered charter (Tham & Ewing, 2007). When a bill of rights is implemented, the judiciary is seen
as the only custodians of human rights, as seen in the US. Tham and Ewing highlight that there
are grave consequences which follow from this assumption which are that legal de isio s
become the key material in interpreting and articulating human rights, and legal expertise will be
seen as necessary for human rights literacy and that such a trajectory threatens to impair the
protection of human rights (2007, p. 465). The committee on Law and Justice of the NSW
Legislative Council shared this sentiment when, in response to Attorney-General the Hon Jeff
Shaw in 1999, argued that a bill of rights would undermine the role of parliament and the courts,
and diminish parliamentary supremacy. The committee further rejected the idea of a bill of rights
on the basis that it would politicise the judiciary as parliamentarians are directly elected by and
a ou ta le to the people, i a a that u ele ted judges are t (Dyer, 2018). Hence, a bill of
rights would provide the judiciary with excessive power which leads to the politicization of the
judiciary.
Furthermore, the rights in a bill at times can conflict with one another and require judicial
interpretation. Zimmerman notes that
rights do u e ts are al a s
ague, aspiratio al
creatures and give no guidance on what interests rank the highest. This leaves plenty of scope
for o k judi ial i terpretatio
(2008, p. 2). The ways in which the judges interpret the right is
vitally influenced by the political environment as well as judicial ethical values which creates
potentiality of biases and inconsistencies. In principle, the enactment of a bill of rights would
allow the courts to have the power to change the existing legislation in a way that will conform
to the judicial rulings (Carrick, 2010). The enactment of the bill of rights would only
o fer o
judges a power to veto legislation retrospectively, on the basis of judgements of political
oralit
(Goldsworthy, 2010, p. 74). The judicial power will only work to diminish the rule of law
rather than enhancing it. Thus, the shift in power to the judges from the elected officials could
be dangerous as the court fails to offer an effective interpretation of the entrenched rights.
Undermines Australia’s federalism
The bill of rights will under i e Australia s federalis
promoting the power of
centrally-appointed judges, imposing extensive restrictions on the ability of the state to exercise
its power (James, 2004). One of the main benefits of federalism in Australia is that power is
distributed in a democratic fashion between states, which means that legislation can be more
responsive to regional requirements. Given that rights are moral and ethical quandaries, it is fair
to say that they are not self-evident and when looking at history, cases brought before judges
regarding rights have often not been black and white. The discrepancy behind the notion of
a io s regardi g hu a
rights is i porta t
he
o sideri g the e te t to
hi h su h
guarantees can co-exist with the pluralistic, different sizes for different States approach that
u derlies a d justifies federalis . (Allan, 2006, p. 186). Allan (2006) refers to this as the
centralising effect that court judgements make under a bill of rights like in the US; a one size fits
all approach. Having a bill of rights seriously curtails the system of balances and checks (Gibbs,
1986) by ignoring the intended benefits of federalism and the necessary distinction required for
individual state requirements.
Promotes a litigious society
The enactment of the bill of rights would allow the present laws and policies to be
challenged and thus encourage frivolous, costly and timely legal actions (Muhlenberg, 2005).
Drawing on from the Canadian case, where a charter of rights was enacted in 1982, it is possible
to see
hat
a lie ahead for Australia s future as the Australia Co
issio 's proposals are
earl ide ti al to pro isio s i the Ca adia Charter (Ferguson, 1990, p. 219). Ferguson states
that the charter has not only increased the number of charter cases by five hundred to a thousand
each year (p. 219), but also: increased lawyers trial preparation time due to the provision of a
s orgas ord of e argu e ts, raisi g osts of litigatio
p. 219) and created a huge backlog
of cases as a result of introduced complexity, stating that the time the supreme court takes to
issue a judgement doubled in the first three years of the charter being enacted (p. 218).
Furthermore, Furedi & Bristow make the claim that a culture of litigation, as found in the UK, only
benefits greedy lawyers as it imposes huge financial and social costs in the way that fear of
litigatio
urtails professio al auto o
, stifles i
o atio a d leads to defe si e pra ti es
(2010, p. 1). The excessively litigious society that a bill of rights would impose on Australia is not
only complex but also very costly to judges, lawyers and society as a whole.
Conclusion
The bill of rights is unnecessary in Australia as it operates well under the current
constitutional democratic system. As it is now, the Australian Constitution captures the rights of
the people despite not being consolidated. Introduction of the law will upset the balance of
power between the judiciary and the legislature. It will give the judiciary more power which will
da age the atio s de o ra . The ill of rights requires effective interpretation, but the
judiciary has little guidance that could help in the process. The outcome of the bill of rights
depends hugely on the ethical view of the judges. The emphasis on groups of rights which the bill
of rights promotes, discriminates against some people and diminishes the individuals rights. It
will also culminate in the increased litigation process that is damaging to the society. Therefore,
the argument presented vividly showcases that there is no reason why Australia needs to adopt
the ill of rights as it
ill se erel da age the atio s de o rati
ourse a d affe t the
constitutional mechanisms as well as promote the concentration of power in the judicial hands.
References
Bill Muhle erg.
. What is ro g ith a ill of rights? , Ne s Weekl Mel our e ,
Retrieved on August 27, 2018 from
http://www.newsweekly.com.au/articles/2005aug13_c.html
Gi
s “ir Harr ,
. A o stitutio al ill of rights . I stitute of Pu li Affairs.
Ja es Alla
. Bills of rights as e tralisi g i stru e ts , Pro eedi gs of the Eightee th
Conference of the Samuel Griffith Society. Canberra. Vol. 18, Chapter 5. Retrieved on
August 27, 2018 from
http://www.samuelgriffith.org.au/papers/html/volume18/v18chap5.html
Jere
Waldro
. A rights-based critique of constitutio al rights , O ford Jour al of
Legal Studies, Vol. 13, No. 1.
AHRC. (n.d.). Legislation . Retrieved from https://www.humanrights.gov.au/ourwork/legal/legislation
Allan, J. (2006). Bills of Rights as Centralising Instruments. Adelaide Law Review , 183-198.
Carrick, B. (2010). Freedom on the Wallaby: A Comparison of Arguments in the Australian Bill of
Rights Debate. The Western Australian Jurist, 68-114.
Chandra, R. (2017). Collective rights vs. Individual rights. International Journal of
Multidisciplinary Research and Development, 51-55.
Charlesworth, H. (2002). Writing in Rights: Australia and the Protection of Human Rights.
Denzin, N. K., & Giardina, M. (2010). Qualitative Inquiry and Human Rights. New York:
Routledge.
Dyer, R. (2018). Should Australia have a Bill of Rights? Retrieved from Evatt Foundation:
http://evatt.org.au/papers/should-australia-have-bill-rights.html
Ferguson, G. (1990). The Impact of an Entrenched Bill of Rights: The Canadian Experience.
Monash University Law Review , 211-227.
Furedi, F., & Bristow, J. (2010). The Social Cost of Litigation. Chichester: Centre for Policy
Studies.
Goldsworthy, J. (2010). Parliamentary Sovereignty: Contemporary Debates. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Huscroft, G., Miller, B. W., & Webber, G. (2014). Proportionality and the Rule of Law: Rights,
Justification, Reasoning. New York: Camebridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1929). Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan and Co.
Law & Justice Foundation. (1997). A Bill of Rights for Australia - But do we need it? Retrieved
from Law and Justice Foundation:
http://www.lawfoundation.net.au/ljf/app/A60DA51D4C6B0A51CA2571A7002069A0.ht
ml
Lucksted, O. D., & Martell, D. F. (1982). Cults: a conflict between religious liberty and
involuntary servitude? West Lafayette: Federal Bureau of Investigation, U.S. Dept. of
Justice.
Mason, S. A. (2006). Why do we need a bill of rights? Retrieved from Centre for Policy
Development: https://cpd.org.au/2006/03/why-do-we-need-a-bill-of-rights/
Nadim, U. (2015). Should Australia Have a Bill of Rights? Retrieved from Sydney Criminal
Lawyers: www.sydneycriminallawyers.com.au/blog/should-australia-have-a-bill-ofrights/
Newton, K., Thannhauser, D., & Jackman, T. (1998). The Preservation and Enhancement of
Individuals' Rights and Freedoms in Queensland: Should Queensland adopt a bill of
rights? Brisbane: Legislative Assemble of Queensland Legal, Constitutional and
Administrative Review Committee.
Pecorino, P. A. (2001). Introduction To Philosophy: an Online Textbook. Queensborough:
Queensborough Community College.
Pretorius, S. (2018). Spiritual Abuse. Acta Theologica, 219-240.
Stone, A. (2002). Disagreement and an Australian Bill of Rights. Melbourne University Law
Review , 478-497.
Tham, J.-C., & Ewing, K. D. (2007). Limitations of a Charter of Rights in the Age of CounterTerrorism. Melbourne University Law Review, 462-498.
Waldron, J. (1999). Law and Disagreement. New York: Oxford University Press.
Williams, G. (2017). A Bill of Rights for Australia? Australian Journal of Human Rights, 1-4.
Zimmermann, A. (2008). The Trouble with a WA Human Rights Act. Perth: Murdoch University .
Peter Hitchens. (2003). The Abolition of Liberty: The Decline of Order and Justice in England.
London: Atlantic Books.