Hypocrisy
Hypocrisy is the practice of feigning to be what one is not or to believe what one does not.[1] The word "hypocrisy" entered the English language c. 1200 with the meaning "the sin of pretending to virtue or goodness".[2] Today, "hypocrisy" often refers to advocating behaviors that one does not practice. However, the term can also refer to other forms of pretense, such as engaging in pious or moral behaviors out of a desire for praise rather than out of genuinely pious or moral motivations.
Definitions of hypocrisy vary. In moral psychology, it is the failure to follow one's own expressed moral rules and principles.[3] According to British political philosopher David Runciman, "other kinds of hypocritical deception include claims to knowledge that one lacks, claims to a consistency that one cannot sustain, claims to a loyalty that one does not possess, claims to an identity that one does not hold".[4] American political journalist Michael Gerson says that political hypocrisy is "the conscious use of a mask to fool the public and gain political benefit".[5]
Hypocrisy has been a subject of folk wisdom and wisdom literature from the beginnings of human history. Increasingly, since the 1980s, it has also become central to studies in behavioral economics, cognitive science, cultural psychology, decision making, ethics, evolutionary psychology, moral psychology, political sociology, positive psychology, social psychology, and sociological social psychology.
Etymology
[edit]The word hypocrisy comes from the Greek ὑπόκρισις (hypokrisis), which means "jealous", "play-acting", "acting out", "coward" or "dissembling".[6] The word hypocrite is from the Greek word ὑποκριτής (hypokritēs), the agentive noun associated with ὑποκρίνομαι (hypokrinomai κρίση, "judgment" »κριτική (kritikē), "critics") presumably because the performance of a dramatic text by an actor was to involve a degree of interpretation, or assessment.
Alternatively, the word is an amalgam of the Greek prefix hypo-, meaning "under", and the verb krinein, meaning "to sift or decide". Thus the original meaning implied a deficiency in the ability to sift or decide. This deficiency, as it pertains to one's own beliefs and feelings, informs the word's contemporary meaning.[7]
Whereas hypokrisis applied to any sort of public performance (including the art of rhetoric), hypokrites was a technical term for a stage actor and was not considered an appropriate role for a public figure. In Athens during the 4th century BC, for example, the great orator Demosthenes ridiculed his rival Aeschines, who had been a successful actor before taking up politics, as a hypocrites whose skill at impersonating characters on stage made him an untrustworthy politician. This negative view of the hypokrites, perhaps combined with the Roman disdain for actors, later shaded into the originally neutral hypokrisis. It is this later sense of hypokrisis as "play-acting", i.e., the assumption of a counterfeit persona, that gives the modern word hypocrisy its negative connotation.
History
[edit]Hypocrisy became a major topic in English political history in the early 18th century. The Toleration Act 1688 allowed for certain rights, but it left Protestant nonconformists (such as Congregationalists and Baptists) deprived of important rights, including that of office-holding. Nonconformists who wanted office ostentatiously took the Anglican sacrament once a year to avoid the restrictions. High Church Anglicans were outraged and outlawed what they called "occasional conformity" in 1711 with the Occasional Conformity Act 1711.[8] In the political controversies using sermons, speeches, and pamphlet wars, high churchmen and Nonconformists attacked their opponents as insincere and hypocritical, as well as dangerously zealous, in contrast to their own moderation.
In his famous book Fable of the Bees (1714) English author Bernard Mandeville (1670–1733) explored the nature of hypocrisy in contemporary European society. On the one hand Mandeville was a ‘moralist’ heir to the French Augustinianism of the previous century, viewing sociability as a mere mask for vanity and pride. On the other he was a ‘materialist’ who helped found modern economics. He tried to demonstrate the universality of human appetites for corporeal pleasures. He argued that the efforts of self-seeking entrepreneurs are the basis of emerging commercial and industrial society, a line of thought that influenced Adam Smith (1723–1790) and 19th century utilitarianism. The tension between these two approaches, modes, ambivalences and contradictions—concerning the relative power of norms and interests, the relationship between motives and behaviours, and the historical variability of human societies.[9] In the Enlightenment of the 18th century, discussions of hypocrisy were common in the works of Voltaire, Rousseau, and Montaigne.[10]
In the 1750 to 1850 era, Whig aristocrats in England boasted of their special benevolence for the common people. They claimed to be guiding and counseling reforms to prevent the outbreaks of popular discontent that caused instability and revolution in Europe. Tory and radical critics accused the Whigs of hypocrisy—alleging they were deliberately using the slogans of reform and democracy to boost themselves into power while preserving their precious aristocratic exclusiveness.
Observers from the Continent commented on the English political culture. Liberal and radical observers noted the servility of the English lower classes, the obsession everyone had with rank and title, the extravagance of the aristocracy, a supposed anti-intellectualism, and a pervasive hypocrisy that extended into such areas as social reform.
United States
[edit]In the propaganda battles of World War II, Japan attacked American hypocrisy by emphasizing the injustice of the incarceration camps for Japanese in the United States. Radio Tokyo emphasized that the camps revealed the hypocritical American claim to democratic ideals and fair play. The propaganda quoted American founding fathers, neutral sources, and dissenting opinions from major American newspapers. Radio Tokyo utilized fictitious sources as well. It proclaimed the moral superiority of Japan while threatening to mistreat American POWs in retaliation.[11]
American historian Martin Jay in The Virtues of Mendacity: On Lying in Politics (2012) explores how writers over the centuries have treated hypocrisy, deception, flattery, lying and cheating, slander, false pretenses, living on borrowed glory, masquerading, conventions of concealment, playacting before others and the arts of dissimulation. He assumes that politics is worthwhile, but since it is unavoidably linked to lying and hypocrisy, Jay concludes that lying must not be all that bad.[12][13]
Moral and religious codes
[edit]Many belief systems condemn hypocrisy.[14]
Buddhism
[edit]In the Buddhist text Dhammapada, Gautama Buddha condemns a man who takes the appearance of an ascetic but is full of passions within.[15]
Christianity
[edit]In some translations of the Book of Job, the Hebrew word chaneph is rendered as "hypocrite", though it usually means "godless" or "profane". In the Christian Bible, Jesus Christ condemns the scribes and Pharisees as hypocrites in the passage known as the Woes of the Pharisees.[16][17] He also denounces hypocrites in more general terms in Matthew 7:5.
In the 16th century, John Calvin was critical of Nicodemites.
Islam
[edit]In Islam, Quranic Chapter 63 is often titled "The Hypocrites". Hypocrisy, called munafiq in Islam, is viewed as a serious sickness.[18] The Qur'an rails against those who claim to be believers and peacemakers, thinking they are fooling God and others, but only fool themselves.[19]
Psychology
[edit]Hypocrisy has long been of interest to psychologists.
Carl Jung
[edit]In Switzerland Carl Jung (1875–1961) attributed hypocrisy to those who are not aware of the dark or shadow-side of their nature. Jung wrote:
- Every individual needs revolution, inner division, overthrow of the existing order, and renewal, but not by forcing them upon his neighbors under the hypocritical cloak of Christian love or the sense of social responsibility or any of the other beautiful euphemisms for unconscious urges to personal power.[20]
Jung went on:[21]
It is under all circumstances an advantage to be in full possession of one's personality, otherwise the repressed elements will only crop up as a hindrance elsewhere, not just at some unimportant point, but at the very spot where we are most sensitive. If people can be educated to see the shadow-side of their nature clearly, it may be hoped that they will also learn to understand and love their fellow men better. A little less hypocrisy and a little more self-knowledge can only have good results in respect for our neighbor; for we are all too prone to transfer to our fellows the injustice and violence we inflict upon our own natures.
In New Paths in Psychology Jung pointedly referred to the "hypocritical pretenses of man". "Dream-analysis above all else mercilessly uncovers the lying morality and hypocritical pretences of man, showing him, for once, the other side of his character in the most vivid light".[22] Jung omitted this characterization from his later essay On the Psychology of the Unconscious, which developed out of the former.
Preference for the effortless
[edit]The best way to cultivate a reputation for fairness is to really be fair. But since it is much harder to be fair than to seem fair, and since laziness is built deep into human nature,[23] humans more often choose appearance over reality.[24]
Self-deception
[edit]"So convenient a thing is it to be a reasonable creature, since it enables one to find or make a reason for everything one has a mind to do."[25] Benjamin Franklin's observation has been confirmed by recent studies in self-deception.[26] In everyday reasoning, humans do little to get real evidence when taking positions or making decisions, and do even less to get evidence for opposing positions. Instead, they tend to fabricate "pseudo-evidence" – often after the decision had already been made ("post hoc fabrication").[27][page needed]
Humans take a position, look for evidence that supports it, then, if they find some evidence – enough so that the position "makes sense" – they stop thinking altogether (the "makes-sense stopping rule").[28] And, when pressed to produce real evidence, they tend to seek and interpret "evidence" that confirms what they already believe (the "confirmation bias").[29]
Moreover, humans tend to think highly of themselves, highlighting strengths and achievements, and overlooking weakness and failures (the "self-serving bias"). When asked to rate themselves on virtues, skills, or other desirable traits (including ethics, intelligence, driving ability, and sexual skills), a large majority say they are above average.[30] Power and privilege magnify the distortion: 94% of college professors think that they do above average work.[31] This effect is weaker in Asian countries and in other cultures which value the group more highly than the self.[32]
Evolutionary psychology
[edit]Evolutionary psychologist Robert Kurzban argues that one's moral modules lead one to condemn infidelity while mating modules induce one to commit it.[33][page needed]
Self-ignorance
[edit]Robert Wright wrote that "Human beings are a species splendid in their array of moral equipment, tragic in their propensity to misuse it, and pathetic in their constitutional ignorance of the misuse."[34] Humans are very good at challenging the beliefs of other people, but when it comes to their own beliefs, they tend to protect them, not challenge them.[35] A consistent finding of psychological research is that humans are fairly accurate in their perceptions of others, but generally inaccurate in their perceptions of themselves.[36] Humans tend to judge others by their behavior, but think they have special information about themselves – that they know what they are "really like" inside – and thus effortlessly find ways to explain away selfish acts, and maintain the illusion that they are better than others.[37]
Social psychology
[edit]Social psychologists have generally viewed hypocrisy as an instantiation of attitudinal and/or behavioral inconsistency.[38] Accordingly, many social psychologists have focused on the role of dissonance in explaining individuals' aversion to hypocritical thinking and behavior.[39] Individuals are motivated to avoid hypocritical stances in order to forestall the negative drive state of dissonance. For example, a dissonance-based study on the use of condoms among young adults showed that induced hypocrisy can lead to increased purchase and use of condoms.[40]
Alternatively, some social psychologists have suggested that individuals view hypocrisy negatively because it suggests that hypocrites are providing a false signal regarding their moral goodness.[41]
Philosophy
[edit]Hypocrisy has been an intermittent topic of interest to philosophers. Niccolò Machiavelli famously noted that "the mass of mankind accept what seems as what is; nay, are often touched more nearly by appearances than by realities".[42] Philosophical issues raised by hypocrisy can be broadly divided into two kinds: metaphysical/conceptual and ethical. Most philosophical commentary on hypocrisy is concerned with the ethical questions it raises: is hypocrisy morally wrong or bad? If it is, is there anything distinctly objectionable about it, or can it be easily subsumed under a broader category of morally objectionable conduct–for example, deceit? Is hypocrisy necessary or desirable for the sake of certain valuable activities–most notably, politics? [43]
Recently, hypocrisy has emerged as a key focus in philosophical discussions of the ethics of blame. It seems that even if a person has violated some moral norm and is genuinely blameworthy for doing so, it is open to them to challenge the blame leveled at them on the grounds that it is hypocritical; a typical expression of this idea is the phrase, "You have no right to blame me!" Accordingly, some philosophers argue that in order to have the standing or entitlement to blame others, one's blame must not be hypocritical. Defenses of this position have usually focused on the connection between hypocrisy and fairness: the basic idea is that the hypocritical blamer in some way fails to treat the target of her blame as a moral equal.[44] Other proposed explanations include the idea that standing in a moral community requires a reciprocal willingness to accept blame, a willingness that hypocrites lack.[45] Patrick Todd argues that all and only those who are committed to the relevant norms possess the standing to blame, and hypocrites lack commitment in the relevant sense.[46] Other philosophers reject the "No-hypocrisy" condition on standing altogether.[47] Typically, these philosophers do not deny that sometimes the wrongness of hypocrisy can outweigh a would-be blamer's entitlement to blame others; but they will insist that this is not invariably the case, and some hypocrites do have standing to blame.[48] R.A. Duff suggests that underlying the disagreement between these two views is a disagreement about the size and scope of moral community, while Kyle Fritz and Daniel Miller suggest that the rejection of the "No-hypocrisy" condition reflects a failure to distinguish between the right to blame and the value of blaming.
The definition of hypocrisy itself is the fundamental question of the relatively new philosophical discussions on hypocrisy. Early answers tended to focus on the deceptive or inconsistent qualities of hypocrisy. For Eva Kittay, for example, the fundamental attribute of hypocrites is "self-referential deception,"[49] and for Gilbert Ryle, to be hypocritical is to "try to appear activated by a motive other than one's real motive."[50] On Dan Turner's view, by contrast, the fundamental feature is "conflict or disparity" between a person's attitudes, where this may or may not involve deception.[51] Bela Szabados and Daniel Statman argue that self-deception is the characteristic attribute of "garden variety of hypocrisies."[52][53] Roger Crisp and Christopher Cowten identify four types of hypocrisy: pretense of moral goodness, moral criticism of others by those possessing faults of their own, failure to satisfy self-acknowledged moral requirements, and a complacent, unreflective commitment to virtues feigned or preached. What unifies these types is a "metavice," a lack of "moral seriousness."[54] More recently, some philosophers–notably, Benjamin Rossi and Fritz and Miller–have defined hypocrisy in terms of dispositions to blame others or to avow commitment to certain norms together with an unwillingness to accept blame from others or to blame themselves.[55][56] Rossi's "Commitment Account of Hypocrisy" addresses paradigmatic cases of hypocrisy that Fritz and Miller's "Differential Blaming Disposition Account" does not include.
Benefits
[edit]Although there are many negatives to hypocrisy, there can be benefits from it as well.[57] There are also benefits from ignoring it. Political theorist Judith N. Shklar argues, in "Let Us Not Be Hypocritical," we are all too eager to construe even minor deviations from our opponents' professed beliefs as hypocrisy, rather than understandable imperfections and weaknesses to which everyone is prone.[58][59]
Political journalist Michael Gerson notes that, "There is often hypocritical deception involved in political and diplomatic negotiations, which generally start with principled, nonnegotiable demands that are negotiated away in the process of finding a compromise." Gerson concludes:[5]
hypocrisy is unavoidable and necessary. If people were required, at all times, to live up to ideals of honesty, loyalty and compassion in order for those ideals to exist, there would be no ideals. Being a moral person is a struggle in which everyone repeatedly fails, becoming a hypocrite in each of those moments. A just and peaceful society depends on hypocrites who ultimately refused to abandon the ideals they betray.
See also
[edit]- Accusation in a mirror – Hate speech incitement technique
- Double standard – Inconsistent application of principles
- Playing the victim – Fabrication or exaggeration of victimhood
- Psychological manipulation – Exploitative type of social influence
- Psychological projection – Attributing parts of the self to others
- The Mote and the Beam – Parable taught by Jesus of Nazareth according to Christian gospels
- The pot calling the kettle black – Proverbial idiom referring to an example of hypocrisy
- Threat – Indication of intent of harm
- Tu quoque – Fallacy regarding hypocrisy
- Whataboutism – Formal fallacy
References
[edit]- ^ "hypocrisy", Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/hypocrisy Archived 5 April 2023 at the Wayback Machine, accessed 5 April 2023
- ^ "hypocrisy (n.)", Online Etymology Dictionary, https://www.etymonline.com/word/hypocrisy#etymonline_v_16134 Archived 1 October 2017 at the Wayback Machine, accessed 5 April 2023
- ^ Lammers, Joris; Stoker, Janka I.; Jordan, Jennifer; Pollmann, Monique; Stapel, Diederik A. (July 2011). "Power increases infidelity among men and women" (PDF). Psychological Science. 22 (9): 1191–1197. doi:10.1177/0956797611416252. PMID 21771963. S2CID 11385458. Archived (PDF) from the original on 17 December 2021. Retrieved 21 September 2020.
- ^ Runciman, David (2010). Political Hypocrisy: The Mask of Power, from Hobbes to Orwell and Beyond. Princeton UP. p. 8. ISBN 978-0691148151.
- ^ a b Gerson, Michael (29 November 2016). "Trump's hypocrisy is good for America". Washington Post. Archived from the original on 29 November 2016. Retrieved 29 November 2016.
- ^ Pocket Oxford Classical Greek Dictionary, ed Morwood and Taylor, OUP 2002
- ^ "Online Etymology Dictionary: "hypocrisy"". Etymonline.com. Archived from the original on 1 October 2017. Retrieved 28 March 2013.
- ^ Jones Clyve (2011). "'Too Wild to Succeed': The Occasional Conformity Bills and the Attempts by the House of Lords to Outlaw the Tack in the Reign of Anne". Parliamentary History. 30 (3): 414–27. doi:10.1111/j.1750-0206.2011.00276.x.
- ^ Luban Daniel (2015). "Bernard Mandeville as Moralist and Materialist". History of European Ideas. 41 (7): 831–57. doi:10.1080/01916599.2015.1010777. S2CID 145179618. Archived from the original on 5 April 2023. Retrieved 31 August 2020.
- ^ Miller James (2014). "Rousseau and Montaigne". Raritan. 33 (4): 158–66. ProQuest 1543039333. Archived from the original on 6 April 2023. Retrieved 6 July 2022.
- ^ Mizuno Takeya (2013). "An Enemy's Talk of 'Justice'". Journalism History. 39 (2): 94. doi:10.1080/00947679.2013.12062905. S2CID 142108853.
- ^ Jay, Martin (2012). The Virtues of Mendacity: On Lying in Politics.
- ^ Bryan Garsten, "Looking for an honest man." Modern Intellectual History 8#3 (2011): 697–708.
- ^ Kasulis, Thomas P. (1993). "Hypocrisy in the Self-Understanding of Religions". Inter-Religious Models and Criteria. pp. 151–165. doi:10.1007/978-1-349-23017-4_9. ISBN 978-1-349-23019-8. Archived from the original on 6 July 2022. Retrieved 6 July 2022.
- ^ "What is the use of platted hair, O fool! what of the raiment of goat-skins? Within thee there is ravening, but the outside thou makest clean. The man who wears dirty raiments, who is emaciated and covered with veins, who lives alone in the forest, and meditates, him I call indeed a Brâhmana. I do not call a man a Brâhmana because of his origin or of his mother. He is indeed arrogant, and he is wealthy: but the poor, who is free from all attachments, him I call indeed a Brâhmana. Dhammapada 394–96, Translated from the Pâli Archived 3 April 2017 at the Wayback Machine by F. Max Müller
- ^ Gospel of Luke 11:37–54 and Gospel of Matthew 23:1–36
- ^ Steve Mason, "Pharisaic Dominance Before 70 CE and the Gospels' Hypocrisy Charge (Matt 23: 2–3)." Harvard Theological Review 83#4 (1990): 363–81.
- ^ Christine Huda Dodge (2009). The Everything Understanding Islam Book: A complete guide to Muslim beliefs, practices, and culture. F+W Media. p. 96. ISBN 9781605507248.
- ^ "And of mankind are some who say, 'We believe in God and the Last Day,' when they believe not. They think to beguile God and those who believe, and they beguile none save themselves; but they perceive not. In their hearts is a disease, and God increases their disease. A painful doom is theirs because they lie. And when it is said to them, 'Make not mischief on the earth,' they say, 'We are only peacemakers.' Behold they are indeed the mischief-makers but they perceive not." Al-Baqara 8–12
- ^ Jung 1966, p. 5.
- ^ Jung 1966, par. 28.
- ^ Jung 1966, par. 437.
- ^ Kahneman, Daniel (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. p. 35.
- ^ Haidt 2006, p. 61.
- ^ "Franklin, B. (1771), p. 18. The Autobiography of Benjamin Franklin. Ushistory.org". Archived from the original on 19 April 2014. Retrieved 17 April 2014.
- ^ Von Hippel, William; Trivers, Robert (February 2011). "The evolution and psychology of self-deception" (PDF). Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 34 (1): 1–16. doi:10.1017/s0140525x10001354. PMID 21288379. Archived from the original (PDF) on 18 April 2013.
- ^ Kuhn, Deanna (1991). The skills of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-40451-7.
- ^ Perkins, D. N.; Farady, Michael; Bushey, Barbara (1991). "Everyday Reasoning and the Roots of Intelligence". In Voss, James F.; Perkins, David N.; Segal, Judith W. (eds.). Informal Reasoning and Education. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. pp. 83–106. doi:10.4324/9780203052228. ISBN 978-0805802085. S2CID 142603608.
- ^ Wason, P.C. (July 1960). "On the Failure to Eliminate Hypotheses in a Conceptual Task". Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology. 12 (3): 129–140. doi:10.1080/17470216008416717. S2CID 19237642.
- ^ Alicke, Mark D.; Klotz, M. L.; Breitenbecher, David L.; Yurak, Tricia J.; Vredenburg, Debbie S. (May 1995). "Personal contact, individuation, and the better-than-average effect". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 68 (5): 804–825. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.68.5.804.
- ^ Cross, K. Patricia (Spring 1977). "Not Can, But Will College Teaching Be Improved?" (PDF). New Directions for Higher Education. 1977 (17): 1–15. doi:10.1002/he.36919771703. Archived (PDF) from the original on 23 September 2020. Retrieved 21 September 2020.
- ^ Heine, Steven J.; Lehman, Darrin R. (August 1999). "Culture, self-discrepancies, and self-satisfaction". Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin. 25 (8): 915–925. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.854.6181. doi:10.1177/01461672992511001. S2CID 11246577. Archived from the original on 7 April 2023. Retrieved 21 September 2020.
- ^ Kurzban, Robert (2010). Why everyone (else) is a hypocrite: Evolution and the modular mind. Princeton UP. doi:10.1515/9781400835997. ISBN 9781400835997. Archived from the original on 6 July 2022. Retrieved 6 July 2022.
- ^ Wright, Robert (1995). The moral animal: Evolutionary psychology and everyday life. New York: Vintage Books. p. 13. ISBN 9780679763994.
- ^ Shaw, Victoria F. (May 1996). "The cognitive processes in informal reasoning". Thinking & Reasoning. 2 (1): 51–80. doi:10.1080/135467896394564.
- ^ Haidt 2006, p. 66.
- ^ Epley, Nicholas; Dunning, David (December 2000). "Feeling "holier than thou": Are self-serving assessments produced by errors in self- or social prediction?". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 79 (6): 861–75. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.79.6.861. PMID 11138757. S2CID 3573819.
- ^ Alicke, Mark D.; Gordon, Ellen; Rose, David (October 2013). "Hypocrisy: What counts?". Philosophical Psychology. 26 (5): 673–701. doi:10.1080/09515089.2012.677397. S2CID 146164276.
- ^ Fried, C. B. (1998). "Hypocrisy and Identification With Transgressions: A Case of Undetected Dissonance Archived 6 July 2022 at the Wayback Machine", 'Basic and Applied Social Psychology', 20(2), 145–154.
- ^ Stone, J.; Aronson, E.; Crain, A. L.; Winslow, M. P.; Fried, C. B. (1994). "Inducing Hypocrisy as a Means of Encouraging Young Adults to Use Condoms". Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin. 20 (1): 116–128. doi:10.1177/0146167294201012.
- ^ Jordan, J. J.; Sommers, R.; Bloom, P.; Rand, D. G. (2017). "Why Do We Hate Hypocrites? Evidence for a Theory of False Signaling". Psychological Science. 28 (3): 356–368. doi:10.1177/0956797616685771. PMID 28107103.
- ^ "Machiavelli, N. (2004), Book 1 Ch 25. Discourses on the First Decade of Titus Livius. Project Gutenberg". Archived from the original on 9 February 2014. Retrieved 17 April 2014.
- ^ Daryl Glaser (2006). "Does Hypocrisy Matter? The Case of U.S. Foreign Policy". Review of International Studies. 32 (2): 251–268. doi:10.1017/S0260210506007017.
- ^ Wallace, R. Jay (Fall 2010). "Hypocrisy, Moral Address, and the Equal Standing of Persons". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 38 (4): 307–341. doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.2010.01195.x. JSTOR 40926873.
- ^ R.A. Duff (2010). "Blame, Moral Standing, and the Legitimacy of the Criminal Trial". Ratio. 23 (2): 123–140. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9329.2010.00456.x.
- ^ Patrick Todd (2017). "A Unified Account of the Moral Standing to Blame". Noûs. 23 (2): 1–28. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9329.2010.00456.x.
- ^ Macalaster Bell (2013). "Standing to Blame: A Critique". Blame: Its Nature and Norms: 263–281. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199860821.003.0014. ISBN 9780199860821. Archived from the original on 6 March 2019. Retrieved 5 March 2019.
- ^ Linda Radzik (2011). "On Minding Your Own Business: Differentiating Accountability Relations within the Moral Community". Social Theory and Practice. 37 (4): 574–598. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract201137434. JSTOR 23558496. Archived from the original on 3 June 2020. Retrieved 16 August 2019.
- ^ Eva Feder Kittay (1982). "On Hypocrisy". Metaphilosophy. 13 (3 & 4): 277–289. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1982.tb00685.x. JSTOR 24435495.
- ^ Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson 1949, 173.
- ^ Dan Turner (1990). "Hypocrisy". Metaphilosophy. 21 (3): 262–269. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9973.1990.tb00528.x.
- ^ Bela Szabados (1979). "Hypocrisy". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 9 (2): 195–210. doi:10.1080/00455091.1979.10716245. JSTOR 40231090. S2CID 246638899.
- ^ Daniel Statman (1997). "Hypocrisy and Self-Deception". Philosophical Psychology. 10 (1): 57–75. doi:10.1080/09515089708573204.
- ^ Roger Crisp and Christopher Cowten (1994). "Hypocrisy and Moral Seriousness". American Philosophical Quarterly. 31 (4): 343–349. JSTOR 20009796.
- ^ Kyle Fritz and Daniel Miller (2015). "Hypocrisy and the Standing to Blame". Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 99 (1): 118–139. doi:10.1111/papq.12104.
- ^ Benjamin Rossi (2018). "The Commitment Account of Hypocrisy". Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. 21 (3): 553–536. doi:10.1007/s10677-018-9917-3. S2CID 150162902.
- ^ Tillyris, Demetris (2016). "The virtue of vice: a defence of hypocrisy in democratic politics". Contemporary Politics. 22 (1): 1–19. doi:10.1080/13569775.2015.1112958. S2CID 146732349. Archived (PDF) from the original on 20 July 2018.
- ^ Koppang Haavard, Martin Mike W (2004). "On Moralizing in Business Ethics". Business & Professional Ethics Journal. 23 (3): 107–14. doi:10.5840/bpej200423319.
- ^ Judith Shklar, "Let us not be hypocritical." Daedalus (1979): 1–25. in JSTOR Archived 30 November 2016 at the Wayback Machine
Works cited
[edit]- Haidt, Jonathan (2006). "The Faults of Others" (PDF). The Happiness Hypothesis. New York: Basic Books. pp. 59–80.
- Jung, Charles G. (1966). Two Essays on Analytical Psychology. Collected Works. Vol. 7. Princeton UP. ISBN 0-691-01782-4.
Further reading
[edit]- Caviola, Lucius; Faulmüller, Nadira (August 2014). "Moral hypocrisy in economic games – how prosocial behavior is shaped by social expectations". Frontiers in Psychology. 5: 897. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00897. PMC 4132261. PMID 25177307.
- la Cour, Anders; Kromann, Joakim (July 2011). "Euphemisms and hypocrisy in corporate philanthropy". Business Ethics: A European Review. 20 (3): 267–279. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8608.2011.01627.x. S2CID 153773218.
- Davidson, Jenny (2004). Hypocrisy & the Politics of Politeness: Manners & Morals from Locke to Austen. Cambridge University Press.
- Fernández, Jordi (2013). "Self-deception and self-knowledge". Philosophical Studies. 162 (2): 379–400. doi:10.1007/s11098-011-9771-9. S2CID 170896976.
- Furia, Peter A. (January 2009). "Democratic citizenship and the hypocrisy of leaders". Polity. 41 (1): 113–133. doi:10.1057/pol.2008.24. S2CID 145561665.
- Greene, Meredith; Low, Kathryn (April 2014). "Public integrity, private hypocrisy, and the moral licensing effect". Social Behavior and Personality. 42 (3): 391–400. doi:10.2224/sbp.2014.42.3.391.
- Lammers, Joris; Stapel, Diederik A.; Galinsky, Adam D. (May 2010). "Power increases hypocrisy moralizing in reasoning, immorality in behavior". Psychological Science. 21 (5): 737–744. doi:10.1177/0956797610368810. JSTOR 41062277. PMID 20483854. S2CID 206585150.
- Laurent, Sean M.; Clark, Brian A. M.; Walker, Stephannie; Wiseman, Kimberly D. (2014). "Punishing hypocrisy: The roles of hypocrisy and moral emotions in deciding culpability and punishment of criminal and civil moral transgressors". Cognition & Emotion. 28 (1): 59–83. doi:10.1080/02699931.2013.801339. PMID 23725235. S2CID 1644336.
- Porcher, José Eduardo (July–December 2014). "Is self-deception pretense?". Manuscrito. 37 (2): 291–332. doi:10.1590/S0100-60452015005000002.
- Renzo, Massimo (July 2014). "Fairness, self-deception and political obligation". Philosophical Studies. 169 (3): 467–488. doi:10.1007/s11098-013-0203-x. hdl:1885/23939. JSTOR 42920430. S2CID 143769845.
- Ross, Lee; Ward, Andrew (1996). "Naive realism in everyday life: Implications for social conflict and misunderstanding" (PDF). In Reed, Edward S.; Turiel, Elliot; Brown, Terrance (eds.). Values and Knowledge. The Jean Piaget Symposium Series. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. pp. 103–135.
- Rustichini, Aldo; Villeval, Marie Claire (November 2014). "Moral hypocrisy, power and social preferences". Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization. 107 (Part A): 10–24. doi:10.1016/j.jebo.2014.08.002. hdl:10419/58984.
- Sommervoll, Dag Einar (2013). "Sweet self-deception". Journal of Economics. 109 (1): 73–88. doi:10.1007/s00712-012-0308-2. hdl:11250/93930. S2CID 154041122.
- Stone, Rebecca (2014). "Unconscionability, exploitation, and hypocrisy". Journal of Political Philosophy. 22 (1): 27–47. doi:10.1111/jopp.12009.
- Szabados, Béla; Soifer, Eldon (2004). Hypocrisy: Ethical Investigations. Broadview Press. ISBN 978-1551115573.
- Vaara, Eero (June 2003). "Post-acquisition integration as sensemaking: Glimpses of ambiguity, confusion, hypocrisy, and politicization". Journal of Management Studies. 40 (4): 859–94. doi:10.1111/1467-6486.00363. hdl:10138/26465.
- Valdesolo, Piercarlo; DeSteno, David (August 2007). "Moral hypocrisy: Social groups and the flexibility of virtue". Psychological Science. 18 (8): 689–90. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2007.01961.x. PMID 17680939. S2CID 41023171.
- Wagner, Tillmann; Lutz, Richard J.; Weitz, Barton A. (December 2009). "Corporate hypocrisy: Overcoming the threat of inconsistent corporate social responsibility perceptions". Journal of Marketing. 73 (6): 77–91. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.463.1501. doi:10.1509/jmkg.73.6.77. S2CID 51790683.
- Wieting, Stephen G. (2016). The Sociology of Hypocrisy: An Analysis of Sport and Religion. Routledge. ISBN 9781317015345.