Jump to content

Limitarianism (ethical)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

This is the current revision of this page, as edited by Orchastrattor (talk | contribs) at 03:46, 14 August 2024 (horseshoe pseudophilosophy, unsourced). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this version.

(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Limitarianism
DescriptionStudy and theory of when there could be moral and ethical justifications for placing limits on the Citizenry by the State, in order to yield certain types of social justice.
SubjectEthics, economics, law, philosophy, political science

Limitarianism refers to several different types of ethical theories. Though limitarianism applies differently to varied fields of study, what is always common is an examination of when it is proper, moral or ethical to interfere and intervene in the lives and freedoms of individuals, in order to benefit society as a whole. It sometimes presents as a principle of distributive justice in economic theories (economic limitarianism). Unlike encompassing systems of political and economic intervention, which seek to make dramatic changes to the social order, limitarianism deals with specific instances and subjects, for which the necessity and justification of intervention may be examined. As its name implies, limitarianism asks the question of how setting certain limits for human beings can lead to positive outcomes.

Early uses of term "limitarianism"

[edit]

The first known use of the term "limitarianism" seems to have been in early Christianity. Christian theological limitarianism teaches that Christ's atonement applies only to the elect (as Calvinism), and not to all humanity (as Christian universalism taught), or of limited atonement and irresistible grace as St. Augustine had taught.

Types of limitarianism in philosophy, political science, and economics

[edit]

Ethical limitarianism

[edit]

Ethical limitarianism is an ethical theory which (1) tries to be a partial account of distributive justice, (2) belongs within the realms of politics rather than morality, (3) is conceived and developed at the level of non-ideal theory, and (4) relies on an instrumental justification.[1][clarification needed]

Democratic limitarianism

[edit]

Democratic limitarianism is a political theory which posits that governments have priority duties to their citizenry to protect it from risk and to ensure independence from fear. Based on such ideas, this political philosophy urges that governments should prioritize protecting the citizens against fear of death or injury from:

  • Domestic threats
  • Foreign threats
  • Social insecurity
  • Environmental hazard

There exists a political movement which advocates for such ideas through principles of prioritization.[2]

Economic limitarianism

[edit]

Economic limitarianism is a school of thought in economics which asserts that social improvement can be attained by the placement of a certain limit on personal wealth. Different modalities have been proposed for the regulation of such a limit. Economic limitarianism differs from socialism in that it does not negate the idea of private property, nor completely bar the accumulation of wealth. It rather sets to determine and enforce a limit on the accumulation thereof, as means of creating a positive change in the economic system of a nation.[3]

The philosopher Ingrid Robeyns has promoted a form of economic limitarianism which proposes a system of social justice via wealth distribution,[4] which bears some similarities to social democracy and socialism.[5] Robeyn's idea of economic limitarianism states that it is morally impermissible to be excessively rich (i.e., have more economic resources than a certain level).[6] The ethical-economic limitarianism[definition needed] of Robeyns would contrast with this view of democratic limitarianism.[clarification needed] In 2016, the European Research Council awarded Robeyns a grant of 2 million Euros for conducting a 5-year research study on limitarianism.[7]

Response and criticism

[edit]

In the year 2021, two articles were published in the Penn Journal of Philosophy Politics and Economics, Volume 16, providing academic analysis of economic limitarianism from different points of view. The articles specifically tackled the version of economic limitarianism promoted by Robeyns, and referred to her work.

In the first article of the two,[8] Karl Meyer proposed extending Robeyns' theories by applying them to corporations. Meyer posited that the problems raised by Robeyns with regard to excess of wealth, were not limited to individuals, but rather were also characteristic of corporations. Thus, it was Meyer's opinion that the wealth of corporations should also be subjected to limitarian laws and regulations.

The second article of the two,[9] written by Timothy J. Nicklas, criticizes Robeyns' views. Nicklas addresses two of Robeyns' claims concerning the benefits of economic limitarianism, specifically that: 1. It is possible to determine a wealth limit which objectively encapsulates "what is needed to have a flourishing life", and 2. That limitarianism would improve the democratic process. Nicklas is not convinced that there could be an over-arching objective economic measure of people's financial needs to assert a 'good life', a criticism already raised earlier by Bluestein.[10] Nicklas also pointed out, that the striving for political power and the abuse thereof shall continue, even if there had been a limit placed on individual wealth.

[edit]

Socialism and communism

[edit]

Socialism and communism can be thought of as extreme forms of economic limitarianism.[citation needed] They call for a revolutionary collectivisation and either complete or very expansive abolition of private property, as means of creating greater social equity. Limitarianism otherwise differs from them in that it tolerates a higher level of inequality.

Sufficientarianism

[edit]

Sufficientarianism is a school of thought in social justice, economics and philosophy, which strives to determine what are the supposed basic needs that should be allotted to human beings in order to guarantee social equity, or at least equality of opportunity.[11][12] Such questions which are asked by Sufficientarianism, have historically been an integral part of democratic theory and socialist theory, as in both exist the belief that the State has a duty to provide the citizenry with certain "needs" and "rights." Both sufficientarianism and limitarianism revolve around the topics of social equity and equality of opportunity. However, while sufficientarianism deals with questions regarding what people should have or need to be granted, limitarianism examines how to place limits of excess on accumulation of wealth.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Volacu, A., Dumitru, A., Assessing Non-intrinsic Limitarianism
  2. ^ Democratic Limitarianism: What and Why. The Limitarian, Citizen 2.0 website, accessed 1/2/2017
  3. ^ Gough I., What Next for Sustainable Development? Our Common Future at Thirty, Chapter 8: Necessities and Luxuries: How to Combine Redistribution with Sustainable Consumption, Monograph Book, https://doi.org/10.4337/9781788975209, July 2019; https://www.etui.org/sites/default/files/2020-09/2019 Brundtland book ch8.pdf
  4. ^ Suzanne Harrington, Limitarianism: Rein in mega-wealthy before it's too late, The Irish Examiner. 19th of November, 2019; https://www.irishexaminer.com/opinion/columnists/arid-30961517.html
  5. ^ Robeyns, Ingrid (2019) (2019). "What, if Anything, is Wrong with Extreme Wealth?". Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 20:3. 20 (3): 251–266. doi:10.1080/19452829.2019.1633734.
  6. ^ Robeyns, Ingrid. "Having too much". Academia.edu.
  7. ^ Justin Weinberg, Philosopher Wins 2 Million Euros To Study "Limitarianism", DailyNous. December 13th, 2016; https://dailynous.com/2016/12/13/philosopher-wins-2-million-euros-study-limitarianism/
  8. ^ Karl Meyer, Corporate Limitarianism, Penn Journal of Philosophy Politics and Economics, Volume 16, Spring 2021; https://repository.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1098&context=spice
  9. ^ Timothy J. Nicklas, Rejecting Ingrid Robeyns’ Defense of Limitarianism, Penn Journal of Philosophy Politics and Economics, Volume 16, Spring 2021; https://repository.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1098&context=spicehttps://repository.upenn.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1099&context=spice
  10. ^ Bluestein, Jonathan (2020), Prosperism, Amazon KDP. ISBN 979-8614831134
  11. ^ Axel Gosseries, Sufficientarianism, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy; 2001 (DOI 10.4324/9780415249126-S112-1). https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/sufficientarianism/v-1
  12. ^ Robert Husbey, Sufficientarianism, POLITICS. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.013.1382  ; https://oxfordre.com/politics/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190228637.001.0001/acrefore-9780190228637-e-1382