Behaviorism: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
m Replaced VE ref names using RefRenamer
Citation bot (talk | contribs)
Added doi-broken-date. | Use this bot. Report bugs. | Suggested by Dominic3203 | Category:Management cybernetics | #UCB_Category 171/234
 
(28 intermediate revisions by 21 users not shown)
Line 1:
{{Short description|Systematic approach to understanding the behavior of humans and other animals}}
{{Distinguish|Behavioralism}}
{{Redirect|Behavior analysis}}
{{Psychology sidebar |basic}}
{{Use American English|date=October 2020}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=October 2020}}
{{Psychology sidebar |basic}}
'''Behaviorism''' ([[Americanis anda Britishsystematic Englishapproach spellingto differences#-our,understand -or|alsothe spelled]]behavior '''behaviourism''')of humans and other animals.<ref>{{citeCite web | urldate=https://www.britannica.com/science/behaviourism-psychology15 |June 2023 |title=Behaviourism &#124; Classical & Operant Conditioning, Reinforcement & Shaping &#124; Britannica | dateurl=15 June 2023 https://www.britannica.com/science/behaviourism-psychology}}</ref> is a systematic approach to understand the behavior of humans and other animals.<ref>{{citeCite journal |last=Araiba |first=Sho |date=June 2019 |title=Current diversification of behaviorism |journal=[[Perspectives on Behavior Science]] |volume=43 |issue=1 |pages=157–175 |doi=10.1007/s40614-019-00207-0|pmid=32440649 |pmc=7198672 |pmid=32440649}}</ref> It assumes that behavior is either a [[reflex]] evokedelicited by the pairing of certain [[antecedent (behavioral psychology)|antecedent stimuli]] in the environment, or a consequence of that individual's history, including especially [[reinforcement (psychology)|reinforcement]] and [[punishment (psychology)|punishment]] [[three-term contingency|contingencies]], together with the individual's current [[motivating operationMotivation|motivational state]] and [[Stimulus control|controlling stimuli]]. Although behaviorists generally accept the important role of [[heredity]] in determining behavior, deriving from Skinner's three levels of selection: phylogeny, ontogeny, and culture,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Tryon |first=Warren W. |date=2002 |title=Expanding the explanatory base of behavior analysis via modern connectionism: Selectionism as a common explanatory core. |url=https://doi.apa.org/doi/10.1037/h0099963 |journal=The Behavior Analyst Today |language=en |volume=3 |issue=1 |pages=104–118 |doi=10.1037/h0099963 |issn=1539-4352}}</ref> they focus primarily on environmental events. The [[cognitive revolution]] of the late 20th century largely replaced behaviorism as an explanatory theory with [[cognitive psychology]], which unlike behaviorism examinesviews internal mental states as explanations for observable behavior.
 
Behaviorism emerged in the early 1900s as a reaction to [[depth psychology]] and other traditional forms of psychology, which often had difficulty making predictions that could be tested experimentally,. butIt was derived from earlier research in the late nineteenth century, such as when [[Edward Thorndike]] pioneered the [[law of effect]], a procedure that involved the use of consequences to strengthen or weaken behavior.
 
With a 1924 publication, [[John B. Watson]] devised methodological behaviorism, which rejected [[introspection|introspective methods]] and sought to understand behavior by only measuring observable behaviors and events. It was not until the 1930s1945 that [[B. F. Skinner]] suggestedproposed that covert behavior—including [[cognition]] and emotions—is[[emotion]]s—are subject to the same controlling variables as observable behavior,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Skinner |first=B.F. |date=1945 |title=The operational analysis of psychological terms. Psychological Review, 52(5), 270–277 |url=https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1946-00034-001 |journal=Psychological Review |volume=52 |issue=5 |pages=270–277 |doi=10.1037/h0062535 |via=APA}}</ref> which became the basis for his philosophy called [[radical behaviorism|''radical'' behaviorism]].<ref name="RadicalBehaviorismCAB">{{citeCite book |last=Chiesa, Mecca |url=http://www.behavior.org/item.php?id=154 |title=Radical Behaviorism: The Philosophy and the Science |authordate=Chiesa,1994 Mecca|publisher=Authors Cooperative, Inc. |isbn=978-0962331145 |pages=1–241|date=1994 |access-date=July 31, 2016 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170904195958/http://www.behavior.org/item.php?id=154 |archive-date=2017-09-04 |url-status=dead}}</ref><ref name="ABA">{{citeCite journal |last1=Dillenburger, Karola |last2=Keenan, Mickey |name-list-style=amp |date=2009 |title=None of the As in ABA stand for autism: Dispelling the myths|author1=Dillenburger, Karola|author2=Keenan, Mickey|name-list-style=amp|journal=Journal of Intellectual and Developmental Disability |volume=34 |issue=2 |pages=193–195|date=2009 |doi=10.1080/13668250902845244 |pmid=19404840 |s2cid=1818966}}</ref> While Watson and [[Ivan Pavlov]] investigated how (conditioned) neutral stimuli elicit reflexes in [[Classical conditioning|respondent conditioning]], Skinner assessed the reinforcement histories of the discriminative (antecedent) stimuli that emits behavior; the techniqueprocess became known as [[operant conditioning]].
 
The application of radical behaviorism—known as [[applied behavior analysis]]—is used in a variety of contexts, including, for example, applied animal behavior and [[organizational behavior management]] to treatment of mental disorders, such as [[autism]] and [[substance abuse]].<ref name="JABA1968">{{citeCite journal|pmc=1310980|title=Some current dimensions of applied behavior analysis|author1last1=Baer, Donald M. |author2last2=Wolf, Montrose M. |author3last3=Risley, Todd R. |date=1968 |title=Some current dimensions of applied behavior analysis |journal=Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis |volume=1 |issue=1|date=1968|pmid=16795165 |pages=91–7 |doi=10.1901/jaba.1968.1-91 |pmc=1310980 |pmid=16795165}}</ref><ref name="APA-Handbook-BehaviorAnalysis">{{citeCite book | editor-lasturl=Maddenhttp://www.apa.org/pubs/books/4311509.aspx | editor-first=Gregory | title=APA Handbook of Behavior Analysis | publisher=American Psychological Association | publication-place=Washington, DC | year=2013 | isbn=978-1-4338-1111-1 | oclceditor-last=771425225Madden |editor-first=Gregory |series=APA Handbooks in Psychology Series; APA Reference Books Collection |publication-place=Washington, urlDC |oclc=http://www.apa.org/pubs/books/4311509.aspx771425225 | access-date=December 24, 2014}}</ref> In addition, while behaviorism and [[cognitive psychology|cognitive]] schools of psychological thought do not agree theoretically, they have complemented each other in the [[cognitive behavioral therapy|cognitive-behaviorbehavioral therapies]], which have demonstrated utility in treating certain pathologies, including simple [[phobia]]s, [[Posttraumatic stress disorder|PTSD]], and [[mood disorders]].{{Citation needed|date=September 2023}}
 
==Branches of behaviorism==
Line 17 ⟶ 16:
* [[Behavioral genetics]]: Proposed in 1869 by [[Francis Galton]], a relative of [[Charles Darwin]]. Galton believed that inherited factors had a significant impact on individuals' behaviors, however did not believe nurturing was not important. Which was later discredited due to association with the eugenics movement - researchers did not want to associate with Nazi politics whether direct or indirect. {{doi|10.3724/sp.j.1041.2008.01073}}
* [[Interbehaviorism]]: Proposed by [[Jacob Robert Kantor]] before [[B. F. Skinner]]'s writings.
* '''Methodological behaviorism'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA-->: [[John B. Watson]]'s behaviorism states that only public events (motor behaviors of an individual) can be objectively observed. Although it was still acknowledged that thoughts and feelings exist, they were not considered part of the science of behavior.<ref name=RadicalBehaviorismCAB/><ref name="Skinner1976">{{citeCite book |last=Skinner |first=BF |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=K7WKkwPzNqsC |title=About Behaviorism |year=1976 |publisher=Random House, Inc. |locationyear=New York1976 |isbn=978-0-394-71618-3 |pagelocation=18New York |urlpage=https://books.google.com/books?id=K7WKkwPzNqsC18}}</ref><ref name=SEP/> It also laid the theoretical foundation for the early approach [[behavior modification]] in the 1970s and 1980s. Often compared to the views of B.F Skinner (radical behaviorism). Methodological behaviorism “representing"representing the logical positivist-derived philosophy of science”science" which is common in science today, radical focuses on the “pragmatist"pragmatist perspective." {{JSTOR|27759016}}
* [[Psychological behaviorism]]: As proposed by Arthur W. Staats, unlike the previous behaviorisms of Skinner, Hull, and Tolman, was based upon a program of human research involving various types of human behavior. Psychological behaviorism introduces new principles of human learning. Humans learn not only by animal learning principles but also by special human learning principles. Those principles involve humans' uniquely huge learning ability. Humans learn repertoires that enable them to learn other things. Human learning is thus cumulative. No other animal demonstrates that ability, making the human species unique.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Muckler |first=Frederick A. |date=June 1963 |title=On the Reason of Animals: Historical Antecedents to the Logic of Modern Behaviorism |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.2466/pr0.1963.12.3.863 |journal=Psychological Reports |volume=12 |issue=3 |pages=863–882 |doi=10.2466/pr0.1963.12.3.863|s2cid=144398380 |issn=0033-2941 |s2cid=144398380}}</ref>
* [[Radical behaviorism]]: Skinner's philosophy is an extension of Watson's form of behaviorism by theorizing that processes within the organism—particularly, private events, such as thoughts and feelings—are also part of the science of behavior, and suggests that environmental variables control these internal events just as they control observable behaviors. Behavioral events may be observable but not all are, some are considered “private”"private": they are accessible and noticed by only the person who is behaving. B.F. Skinner described behavior as the name for the part of the functioning of the organism that consists of its interacting or having commerce with its surrounding environment. In simple terms, how an individual interacts with its surrounding environment.[https://doi.org/10.1007/BF03395771 [RB<nowiki>]</nowiki>] Although private events cannot be directly seen by others, they are later determined through the species' overt behavior. Radical behaviorism forms the core philosophy behind [[applied behavior analysis|behavior analysis]]. [[Willard Van Orman Quine]] used many of radical behaviorism's ideas in his study of knowledge and language.<ref name=Skinner1976/>
* [[Teleological behaviorism]]: Proposed by [[Howard Rachlin]], post-Skinnerian, purposive, close to [[microeconomics]]. Focuses on objective observation as opposed to cognitive processes.
* [[Theoretical behaviorism]]: Proposed by [[J. E. R. Staddon]],<ref name="Staddon2014">Staddon, John (2014) ''The New Behaviorism'' (2nd edition). Philadelphia, PA: Psychology Press.</ref><ref>Staddon, John (2016) ''The Englishman: Memoirs of a psychobiologist.'' University of Buckingham Press.</ref><ref>{{citeCite journal |last=Malone |first=John C. |date=July 2004 |title=Modern molar behaviorism and theoretical behaviorism: religion and science |journal=[[Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior]] |volume=82 |issue=1 |pages=95–102 |doi=10.1901/jeab.2004.82-95 |pmc=1284997}}</ref> adds a concept of internal state to allow for the effects of context. According to theoretical behaviorism, a state is a set of equivalent histories, i.e., past histories in which members of the same stimulus class produce members of the same response class (i.e., B. F. Skinner's concept of the operant). Conditioned stimuli are thus seen to control neither stimulus nor response but state. Theoretical behaviorism is a logical extension of Skinner's class-based (generic) definition of the operant.
Two subtypes of theoretical behaviorism are:
* [[Clark L. Hull|Hullian]] and post-Hullian: theoretical, group data, not dynamic, physiological
Line 28 ⟶ 27:
===Modern-day theory: radical behaviorism===
{{main|Radical behaviorism}}
B. F. Skinner proposed radical behaviorism as the conceptual underpinning of the [[experimental analysis of behavior]]. This viewpoint differs from other approaches to behavioral research in various ways, but, most notably here, it contrasts with methodological behaviorism in accepting feelings, states of mind and introspection as behaviors also subject to scientific investigation. Like methodological behaviorism, it rejects the reflex as a model of all behavior, and it defends the science of behavior as complementary to but independent of physiology. Radical behaviorism overlaps considerably with other western philosophical positions, such as American [[pragmatism]].<ref>{{citeCite journal |last=Moxley |first=R.A. |year=2004 |title=Pragmatic selectionism: The philosophy of behavior analysis |url=http://www.baojournal.com |format=PDF |journal=The Behavior Analyst Today |volume=5 |issue=1 |pages=108–25 |urldoi=http:/10.1037/www.baojournal.com |format=PDFh0100137 |access-date=2008-01-10|doi=10.1037/h0100137 }}</ref>
 
Although John B. Watson mainly emphasized his position of methodological behaviorism throughout his career, Watson and Rosalie Rayner conducted the infamous [[Little Albert experiment]] (1920), a study in which [[Ivan Pavlov]]'s [[Classical conditioning#Forward conditioning|theory]] to respondent conditioning was first applied to eliciting a fearful reflex of crying in a human infant, and this became the launching point for understanding covert behavior (or private events) in ''radical'' behaviorism.;<ref name=JEAB2010/> Howeverhowever, Skinner felt that aversive stimuli should only be experimented on with animals and spoke out against Watson for testing something so controversial on a human.{{citation needed|date=September 2024}}
 
In 1959, Skinner observed the emotions of two pigeons by noting that they appeared angry because their feathers ruffled. The pigeons were placed together in an operant chamber, where they were aggressive as a consequence of previous [[reinforcement (psychology)|reinforcement]] in the environment. Through [[stimulus control]] and subsequent discrimination training, whenever Skinner turned off the green light, the pigeons came to notice that the food [[extinction (psychology)|reinforcer is discontinued]] following each peck and responded without aggression. Skinner concluded that humans also learn aggression and possess such emotions (as well as other private events) no differently than do nonhuman animals.{{citation needed|date=September 2024}}
 
==Experimental and conceptual innovations==
 
As experimental behavioural psychology is related to [[behavioral neuroscience]], we can date the first researches in the area were done in the beginning of 19th century.<ref>Behavioral Neuroscience, APA, 1807</ref> Later, this essentially philosophical position gained strength from the success of Skinner's early experimental work with rats and pigeons, summarized in his books ''The Behavior of Organisms'' and ''Schedules of Reinforcement.''<ref name="Skinner1938 Organisms">{{citeCite book |last= Skinner |first=B.F. |author-link= B.F. Skinner |title=The Behavior of Organisms |title-link=The Behavior of Organisms |publisher=[[Appleton-Century-Crofts]] |year=1938 |page=473 |isbn=978-0-87411-487-4|title-link=The Behavior of Organisms |publication-place= New York, NY |page=473}}</ref> and ''Schedules of Reinforcement''.<ref>{{citeCite book |author1last1=Cheney, Carl D. |author2=Ferster, Charles B. |title=Schedules of Reinforcement (B.F. Skinner Reprint Series) |last2=Ferster, Charles B. |publisher=Copley Publishing Group |location=Acton, MA |year=1997 |page=758 |isbn=978-0-87411-828-5 |location=Acton, MA |page=758}}</ref> Of particular importance was his concept of the operant response, of which the canonical example was the rat's lever-press. In contrast with the idea of a physiological or reflex response, an operant is a class of structurally distinct but functionally equivalent responses. For example, while a rat might press a lever with its left paw or its right paw or its tail, all of these responses operate on the world in the same way and have a common consequence. Operants are often thought of as species of responses, where the individuals differ but the class coheres in its function-shared consequences with operants and reproductive success with species. This is a clear distinction between Skinner's theory and [[S–R theory]].
As experimental behavioural psychology is related to [[behavioral neuroscience]], we can date the first researches in the area were done in the beginning of 19th century.<ref>Behavioral Neuroscience, APA, 1807</ref>
 
Skinner's empirical work expanded on earlier research on [[trial-and-error]] learning by researchers such as Thorndike and Guthrie with both conceptual reformulations—Thorndike's notion of a stimulus-response "association" or "connection" was abandoned; and methodological ones—the use of the "free operant", so-called because the animal was now permitted to respond at its own rate rather than in a series of trials determined by the experimenter procedures. With this method, Skinner carried out substantial experimental work on the effects of different schedules and rates of reinforcement on the rates of operant responses made by rats and pigeons. He achieved remarkable success in training animals to perform unexpected responses, to emit large numbers of responses, and to demonstrate many empirical regularities at the purely behavioral level. This lent some credibility to his conceptual analysis. It is largely his conceptual analysis that made his work much more rigorous than his peers, a point which can be seen clearly in his seminal work ''Are Theories of Learning Necessary?'' in which he criticizes what he viewed to be theoretical weaknesses then common in the study of psychology. An important descendant of the experimental analysis of behavior is the [[Society for Quantitative Analysis of Behavior]].<ref>{{citeCite journal |last=Commons |first=M.L. |year=2001 |title=A short history of the Society for the Quantitative Analysis of Behavior |url=http://www.baojournal.com |format=PDF |journal=Behavior Analyst Today |volume=2 |issue=3 |pages=275–9 |urldoi=http:10.1037//www.baojournal.com |format=PDFh0099944 |access-date=2008-01-10|doi=10.1037/h0099944 }}</ref><ref>{{citeCite journal |last1last= Thornbury |first1first= Scott |date=1998 |title=The Lexical Approach: A journey without maps|journal=Modern English Teacher|date=1998|volume=7 | issue = 4 |pages= 7–13| url= http://nebula.wsimg.com/9129eed8a13130f4ee92cf2c3ce5b13e?AccessKeyId=186A535D1BA4FC995A73&disposition=0&alloworigin=1 |journal=Modern English Teacher |volume=7 |issue=4 |pages=7–13}}</ref>
Later, this essentially philosophical position gained strength from the success of Skinner's early experimental work with rats and pigeons, summarized in his books ''The Behavior of Organisms''<ref name="Skinner1938 Organisms">{{cite book |last= Skinner |first=B.F. |author-link= B.F. Skinner |title=The Behavior of Organisms |publisher=[[Appleton-Century-Crofts]] |year=1938 |page=473 |isbn=978-0-87411-487-4|title-link=The Behavior of Organisms |publication-place= New York, NY}}</ref> and ''Schedules of Reinforcement''.<ref>{{cite book |author1=Cheney, Carl D. |author2=Ferster, Charles B. |title=Schedules of Reinforcement (B.F. Skinner Reprint Series) |publisher=Copley Publishing Group |location=Acton, MA |year=1997 |page=758 |isbn=978-0-87411-828-5}}</ref> Of particular importance was his concept of the operant response, of which the canonical example was the rat's lever-press. In contrast with the idea of a physiological or reflex response, an operant is a class of structurally distinct but functionally equivalent responses. For example, while a rat might press a lever with its left paw or its right paw or its tail, all of these responses operate on the world in the same way and have a common consequence. Operants are often thought of as species of responses, where the individuals differ but the class coheres in its function-shared consequences with operants and reproductive success with species. This is a clear distinction between Skinner's theory and [[S–R theory]].
 
Skinner's empirical work expanded on earlier research on [[trial-and-error]] learning by researchers such as Thorndike and Guthrie with both conceptual reformulations—Thorndike's notion of a stimulus-response "association" or "connection" was abandoned; and methodological ones—the use of the "free operant", so-called because the animal was now permitted to respond at its own rate rather than in a series of trials determined by the experimenter procedures. With this method, Skinner carried out substantial experimental work on the effects of different schedules and rates of reinforcement on the rates of operant responses made by rats and pigeons. He achieved remarkable success in training animals to perform unexpected responses, to emit large numbers of responses, and to demonstrate many empirical regularities at the purely behavioral level. This lent some credibility to his conceptual analysis. It is largely his conceptual analysis that made his work much more rigorous than his peers, a point which can be seen clearly in his seminal work ''Are Theories of Learning Necessary?'' in which he criticizes what he viewed to be theoretical weaknesses then common in the study of psychology. An important descendant of the experimental analysis of behavior is the [[Society for Quantitative Analysis of Behavior]].<ref>{{cite journal |last=Commons |first=M.L. |year=2001 |title=A short history of the Society for the Quantitative Analysis of Behavior |journal=Behavior Analyst Today |volume=2 |issue=3 |pages=275–9 |url=http://www.baojournal.com |format=PDF |access-date=2008-01-10|doi=10.1037/h0099944 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1= Thornbury |first1= Scott|title=The Lexical Approach: A journey without maps|journal=Modern English Teacher|date=1998|volume=7 | issue = 4 |pages= 7–13| url= http://nebula.wsimg.com/9129eed8a13130f4ee92cf2c3ce5b13e?AccessKeyId=186A535D1BA4FC995A73&disposition=0&alloworigin=1}}</ref>
 
==Relation to language==
As Skinner turned from experimental work to concentrate on the philosophical underpinnings of a science of behavior, his attention turned to human language with his 1957 book ''[[Verbal Behavior]]''<ref>{{citeCite book |last=Skinner |first=Burrhus Frederick |last=Skinner |title=Verbal Behavior |location=Acton, Massachusetts |publisher=Copley Publishing Group |year=1957 |isbn= 978-1-58390-021-5 |location=Acton, Massachusetts}}</ref> and other language-related publications;<ref name="Skinner1969 Contingencies of reinforcement">{{citeCite book | last=Skinner | first=B. F. | title=Contingencies of reinforcement: a theoretical analysis | publisher=Prentice Hall | publication-place=Englewood Cliffs, N.J | year=1969 | isbn=978-0-13-171728-2 | oclcpublication-place=12726275Englewood |Cliffs, N.J |pages=133–157 | chapter=An operant analysis of problem-solving |oclc=12726275}}</ref> ''Verbal Behavior'' laid out a vocabulary and theory for functional analysis of verbal behavior, and was strongly criticized in a review by [[Noam Chomsky]].<ref>{{citeCite journal |last1=Chomsky, Noam |author-link1=Noam Chomsky |last2=Skinner, B.F. |year=1959 |title=A Review of B.F. Skinner's Verbal Behavior |journal=Language |issue=1 |url=http://www.chomsky.info/articles/1967----.htm |yearurl-status=1959dead |pagesjournal=26–58Language |author1volume=Chomsky,35 Noam|issue=1 |author-link1pages=Noam Chomsky26–58 |doi=10.2307/411334 |volume=35 |jstor=411334 |author2=Skinner, B.F. |access-date=9 May 2008 |archive-date=29 September 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150929070654/http://www.chomsky.info/articles/1967----.htm |urlarchive-statusdate=dead29 September 2015 |access-date=9 May 2008}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite book |last=Kennison |first=Shelia M.|year=2013 |title= Introduction to language development |locationpublisher=LosSAGE AngelesPublications |publisheryear=2013 SAGE Publications| isbn=9781483315324 9781483315324|location=Los Angeles}}</ref>
 
Skinner did not respond in detail but claimed that Chomsky failed to understand his ideas,<ref>{{citeCite journal |last= Skinner| |first= B.F. |year=1972 |title=I Have Been Misunderstood. |journal=Center Magazine |year=1972 |issue= March–April |page=63}}</ref> and the disagreements between the two and the theories involved have been further discussed.<ref name="MacCorquodale1970">{{citeCite journal |last=MacCorquodale |first=K. |year=1970 |title=On Chomsky's Review of Skinner's VERBAL BEHAVIOR |url=https://www.behavior.org/computer-modeling/maccorquodale/maccorquodale2.cfm |url-status=dead |journal=Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior |volume=13 |issue=1 |pages=83–99 |url=https://www.behavior.org/computer-modeling/maccorquodale/maccorquodale2.cfm |access-date=2008-01-10 |doi=10.1901/jeab.1970.13-83 |pmc=1333660 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090106061500/http://www.behavior.org/computer-modeling/maccorquodale/maccorquodale2.cfm |archive-date=2009-01-06 |urlaccess-statusdate=dead 2008-01-10}}</ref><ref name="pmid2103585">{{citeCite journal |last= Stemmer| |first= N. |year=1990 |title=Skinner's verbal behavior, Chomsky's review, and mentalism |journal=J Exp Anal Behav |volume=54 |issue=3 |pages=307–15 |year=1990 |pmid=2103585 |doi=10.1901/jeab.1990.54-307 |pmc=1323000 |pmid=2103585}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Palmer |first=David C |date=2006 |title=On Chomsky's Appraisal of Skinner's Verbal Behavior: A Half Century of Misunderstanding |journal=The Behavior Analyst |volume=29 |issue=2 |pages=253–267 |doi=10.1007/BF03392134 |issn=0738-6729 |pmc=2223153 |pmid=22478467|doi=10.1007/BF03392134}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Palmer |first=David C. |date=2000 |title=Chomsky's nativism: A critical review |journal=The Analysis of Verbal Behavior |volume=17 |pages=39–50 |doi=10.1007/BF03392954 |issn=0889-9401 |pmc=2755455 |pmid=22477212|doi=10.1007/BF03392954}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Virués-Ortega |first=Javier |date=2006 |title=The Case Against B. F. Skinner 45 years Later: An Encounter with N. Chomsky |journal=The Behavior Analyst |volume=29 |issue=2 |pages=243–251 |doi=10.1007/BF03392133 |issn=0738-6729 |pmc=2223151 |pmid=22478466|doi=10.1007/BF03392133}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Adelman |first=Barry Eshkol |date=December 2007 |title=An Underdiscussed Aspect of Chomsky (1959) |journal=The Analysis of Verbal Behavior |volume=23 |issue=1 |pages=29–34 |doi=10.1007/BF03393044 |issn=0889-9401 |pmc=2774611 |pmid=22477378|doi=10.1007/BF03393044}}</ref> [[Innateness hypothesis|Innateness theory]], which has been heavily critiqued,<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Chater |first1=Nick |last2=Christiansen |first2=Morten H. |date=October 2008 |title=Language as shaped by the brain |journal=Behavioral and Brain Sciences |volume=31 |issue=5 |pages=489–509 |citeseerx=10.1.1.379.3136 |doi=10.1017/S0140525X08004998|pmid=18826669 |issn=1469-1825 |citeseerxpmid=10.1.1.379.313618826669}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Levinson |first1=Stephen C. |last2=Evans |first2=Nicholas |date=October 2009 |title=The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science |journal=Behavioral and Brain Sciences |volume=32 |issue=5 |pages=429–448 |doi=10.1017/S0140525X0999094X|pmid=19857320 |issn=1469-1825 |pmid=19857320 |doi-access=free |hdl-access=free |hdl=11858/00-001M-0000-0012-C29E-4|hdl-access=free}}</ref> is opposed to behaviorist theory which claims that language is a set of habits that can be acquired by means of conditioning.<ref>{{citeCite book | last1last=Thornbury Thornbury| first1first=Scott Scott| title= An A-Z of ELT |date=2006 |publisher=Macmillan|location=Oxford |isbn=978-1405070638 |location=Oxford |page=24}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite book |last1last=Douglas Brown |first1first= H| |title= Principles of Language Learning and Teaching |date=2000 |publisher=Longman/Pearson Education|location=White Plains |isbn= 978-0-13-017816-9 | pagesedition=Fourth 8–9| editionlocation=White FourthPlains |pages=8–9}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Nicoladis |first1=Elena |last2=Sturdy |first2=Christopher B. |date=2017 |title=How Much of Language Acquisition Does Operant Conditioning Explain? |journal=Frontiers in Psychology |language=en |volume=8 |pages=1918 |doi=10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01918 |pmidissn=291632951664-1078 |pmc=5671510 |issnpmid=1664-107829163295 |doi-access=free}}</ref> According to some, the behaviorist account is a process which would be too slow to explain a phenomenon as complicated as language learning. What was important for a behaviorist's analysis of human behavior was not [[language acquisition]] so much as the interaction between language and overt behavior. In an essay republished in his 1969 book ''Contingencies of Reinforcement'',<ref name="Skinner1969 Contingencies of reinforcement" /> Skinner took the view that humans could construct linguistic stimuli that would then acquire control over their behavior in the same way that external stimuli could. The possibility of such "instructional control" over behavior meant that contingencies of reinforcement would not always produce the same effects on human behavior as they reliably do in other animals. The focus of a radical behaviorist analysis of human behavior therefore shifted to an attempt to understand the interaction between instructional control and contingency control, and also to understand the behavioral processes that determine what instructions are constructed and what control they acquire over behavior. Recently, a new line of behavioral research on language was started under the name of [[relational frame theory]].<ref name="Blackledge">Blackledge, J. T. (2003). An introduction to relational frame theory: Basics and applications. ''The Behavior Analyst Today, 3''(4), 421-433.[https://doi.org/10.1037/h0099997]</ref><ref name="Dymond-2010">{{Cite journal |last1=Dymond |first1=Simon |last2=May |first2=Richard J |last3=Munnelly |first3=Anita |last4=Hoon |first4=Alice E |date=2010 |title=Evaluating the Evidence Base for Relational Frame Theory: A Citation Analysis |journal=The Behavior Analyst |volume=33 |issue=1 |pages=97–117 |doi=10.1007/BF03392206 |issn=0738-6729 |pmc=2867509 |pmid=22479129|doi=10.1007/BF03392206}}</ref><ref name="Rehfeldt-2011">{{Cite journal |last=Rehfeldt |first=Ruth Anne |date=2011 |title=Toward a Technology of Derived Stimulus Relations: An Analysis of Articles Published in the Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 1992–2009 |journal=Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis |volume=44 |issue=1 |pages=109–119 |doi=10.1901/jaba.2011.44-109 |issn=0021-8855 |pmc=3050465 |pmid=21541138|title=Toward a Technology of Derived Stimulus Relations: An Analysis of Articles Published in the Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 1992–2009}}</ref><ref>Martin O'Connor, Lynn Farrell, Anita Munnelly, Louise McHugh. (2017). Citation analysis of relational frame theory: 2009–2016. Journal of Contextual Behavioral Science, Volume 6, Issue 2, Pages 152-158.[https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jcbs.2017.04.009]</ref>
 
==Education==
{{See also|Philosophy of education#Realism}}
B. F. Skinner's book ''[[Verbal Behavior]]'' (1957) does not quite emphasize on language development, but to understand human behavior. Additionally, his work serves in understanding social interactions in the child's early developmental stages focusing on the topic of caregiver-infant interaction.<ref name="McLaughlin 2010 114–131">{{Cite journal |last=McLaughlin |first=Scott F. |date=2010 |title=Verbal behavior by B.F. Skinner: Contributions to analyzing early language learning. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/h0100272 |journal=The Journal of Speech and Language Pathology – Applied Behavior Analysis |language=en |volume=5 |issue=2 |pages=114–131 |doi=10.1037/h0100272 |issn=1932-4731}}</ref> Skinner's functional analysis of verbal behavior terminology and theories is commonly used to understand the relationship between language development but was primarily designed to describe behaviors of interest and explain the cause of those behaviors.<ref name="McLaughlin 2010 114–131" /> [[Noam Chomsky]], an American linguistic professor, has criticized and questioned Skinner's theories about the possible suggestion of parental tutoring in language development. However, there is a lack of supporting evidence where Skinner makes the statement.<ref name="McLaughlin 2010 114–131" /> Understanding language is a complex topic but can be understood through the use of two theories: innateness and acquisition. Both theories offer a different perspective whether language is inherently "acquired" or "learned".<ref>{{Citation |last=Ariew |first=André |title=INNATENESS |date=2007 |work=Philosophy of Biology |pages=567–584 |url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/B9780444515438500265 |access-date=2023-12-09 |publisher=Elsevier |language=en |doi=10.1016/b978-044451543-8/50026-5 |isbn=978-0-444-51543-8}}</ref>
 
Understanding language is a complex topic, but can be understood through the use of two theories: Innateness and acquisition. Both theories offer a different perspective whether language is inherently "acquired" or "learned."<ref>{{Citation |last=Ariew |first=André |title=INNATENESS |date=2007 |url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/B9780444515438500265 |work=Philosophy of Biology |pages=567–584 |access-date=2023-12-09 |publisher=Elsevier |language=en |doi=10.1016/b978-044451543-8/50026-5 |isbn=978-0-444-51543-8}}</ref>
 
==Operant conditioning==
{{main|Operant conditioning||}}
 
[[Operant conditioning]] was developed by [[B.F. Skinner]] in 1938 and is form of learning in which the frequency of a behavior is controlled by consequences to change behavior.<ref name="Murphy 165–194">{{Citation |last1=Murphy |first1=Eric S. |title=Basic Principles of Operant Conditioning |date=2014-05-19 |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781118468135.ch8 |work=The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Operant and Classical Conditioning |pages=165–194 |editor-last=McSweeney |editor-first=Frances K. |editor-last2=Murphy |editor-first2=Eric S. |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781118468135.ch8 |access-date=2023-12-09 |edition=1 |publisher=Wiley |language=en |doi=10.1002/9781118468135.ch8 |isbn=978-1-118-46818-0 |last2=Lupfer |first2=Gwen J. |editor2-last=Murphy |editor2-first=Eric S.}}</ref><ref name="Skinner1938 Organisms" /><ref>W. K. Honig & J. E. R. Staddon (Eds.), 1977, ''Handbook of operant behavior.'' Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.</ref><ref>Staddon, J. E. R. (2016) ''Adaptive Behavior and Learning,'' 2nd edition. Cambridge University Press.</ref> In other words, behavior is controlled by historical consequential contingencies, particularly [[reinforcement]]—a stimulus that increases the probability of performing behaviors, and [[Punishment (psychology)|punishment]]—a stimulus that decreases such probability.<ref name="Murphy 165–194" /> The core tools of consequences are either positive (presenting stimuli following a response), or negative (withdrawn stimuli following a response).<ref>{{Cite news |urldate=https://www.learning2015-theories.com/operant06-conditioning-skinner.html19 |title=Classical and Operant Conditioning - Behaviorist Theories |dateurl=2015https://www.learning-06theories.com/operant-19|work=Learningconditioning-skinner.html Theories|access-date=2017-08-04 |work=Learning Theories}}</ref>
 
The following descriptions explains the concepts of four common types of consequences in operant conditioning:<ref name="CooperABA">{{citeCite book |last1=Cooper |first1=John O. |url=https://www.pearson.com.au/products/A-C-Cooper-John-O-et-al/A-C-Cooper-J-et-al/Applied-Behavior-Analysis-Global-Edition/9781292324630?R=9781292324630 |last1title=Cooper|first1=JohnApplied O.Behavior Analysis |last2=Heron |first2=Timothy E. |last3=Heward |first3=William L. |titledate=AppliedSeptember Behavior12, 2019 Analysis|edition=3|publisher=[[Pearson plc|Pearson]] |dateisbn=September9781292324630 12,|edition=3 2019|pages=1–1056|isbn=9781292324630}}</ref>
* '''Positive reinforcement''': Providing a stimulus that an individual enjoys, seeks, or craves, in order to reinforce desired behaviors.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Chance |first=Paul |title=Learning and Behavior |publisher=Jon-David Hague |year=2014 |isbn=978-1-111-83277-3 |location=Belmont, CA |pages=133}}</ref> For example, when a person is teaching a dog to sit, they pair the command "sit" with a treat. The treat is the positive reinforcement to the behavior of sitting. The key to making positive reinforcement effect is to reward the behavior immediately.
* '''Negative reinforcement''': Increases the frequency of a behavior, but the behavior results from removing unpleasant or unwanted stimulus.<ref name="Murphy 165–194" /> For example, a child hates being nagged (negative) to clean his room (behavior) which increases the frequency of the child cleaning his room to prevent his mother from nagging. Another example would be putting on sunscreen (behavior) before going outside to prevent sunburn (negative).
* '''Positive punishment''': Providing a stimulus that an individual does not desire to decrease undesired behaviors. For example, if a child engages in an undesired behavior, then parents may spank (stimulus) the child to correct their behavior.
* '''Negative punishment''': Removing a stimulus that an individual desires in order to decrease undesired behaviors. An example of this would be grounding a child for failing a test. Grounding in this example is taking away the child's ability to play video games. As long as it is clear that the ability to play video games was taken away because they failed a test, this is negative punishment. The key here is the connection to the behavior and the result of the behavior.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Li |first=Pamela |date=2020-01-14 |title=What is Negative Punishment (Examples and Effectiveness) |url=https://www.parentingforbrain.com/negative-punishment/ |access-date=2021-03-21 |website=Parenting For Brain |language=en-US}}</ref>
Line 74 ⟶ 69:
==Respondent conditioning==
{{main|Classical conditioning}}
Although [[operant conditioning]] plays the largest role in discussions of behavioral mechanisms, [[classical conditioning|respondent conditioning]] (also called Pavlovian or classical conditioning) is also an important behavior-analytic process that needs not refer to mental or other internal processes. Pavlov's experiments with dogs provide the most familiar example of the classical conditioning procedure. In the beginning, the dog was provided meat (unconditioned stimulus, UCS, naturally elicit a response that is not controlled) to eat, resulting in increased salivation (unconditioned response, UCR, which means that a response is naturally caused by UCS). Afterward, a bell ring was presented together with food to the dog. Although bell ring was a neutral stimulus (NS, meaning that the stimulus did not have any effect), dog would start to salivate when only hearing a bell ring after a number of pairings. Eventually, the neutral stimulus (bell ring) became conditioned. Therefore, salivation was elicited as a conditioned response (the response same as the unconditioned response), pairing up with meat—the conditioned stimulus) <ref>{{citeCite web |title=Ivan Pavlov |url=http://www.ivanpavlov.com/ |access-date=16 April 2012}}</ref> Although Pavlov proposed some tentative physiological processes that might be involved in classical conditioning, these have not been confirmed.<ref>{{citeCite journal | last=Bitterman | first=M. E. |year=2006 |title=Classical conditioning since Pavlov | journal=Review of General Psychology | publisher=SAGE Publications | volume=10 | issue=4 | yearpages=2006365–376 | issn=1089-2680 | doi=10.1037/1089-2680.10.4.365 | pagesissn=365–376|1089-2680 |s2cid=144362212 }}</ref> The idea of classical conditioning helped behaviorist John Watson discover the key mechanism behind how humans acquire the behaviors that they do, which was to find a natural reflex that produces the response being considered.
 
[[John B. Watson|Watson]]'s "Behaviourist Manifesto" has three aspects that deserve special recognition: one is that psychology should be purely objective, with any interpretation of conscious experience being removed, thus leading to psychology as the "science of behaviour"; the second one is that the goals of psychology should be to predict and control behaviour (as opposed to describe and explain conscious mental states); the third one is that there is no notable distinction between human and non-human behaviour. Following Darwin's theory of evolution, this would simply mean that human behaviour is just a more complex version in respect to behaviour displayed by other species.<ref>Richard Gross, Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour</ref>
Line 80 ⟶ 75:
==In philosophy==
{{main|Logical behaviorism}}
Behaviorism is a psychological movement that can be contrasted with [[philosophy of mind]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Schlinger |first=Henry D. |date=2009-07-01 |title=Theory of Mind: An Overview and Behavioral Perspective |url=https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1029&context=tpr |journal=The Psychological Record |volume=59 |issue=3 |pages=435–448 |doi=10.1007/BF03395673|s2cid=145671713 |issn=2163-3452 |urls2cid=https://opensiuc.lib.siu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1029&context=tpr145671713}}</ref><ref>Moore, J. (2013). Mentalism as a Radical Behaviorist Views It — Part 1. The Journal of Mind and Behavior. Vol. 34, No. 2, pp. 133-164.[https://www.jstor.org/stable/43854332?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents]</ref><ref>Moore, J. (2013). Mentalism as a Radical Behaviorist Views It — Part 2. The Journal of Mind and Behavior. Vol. 34, No. 3/4, pp. 205-232.[https://www.jstor.org/stable/43854394?seq=1#page_scan_tab_contents]</ref> The basic premise of behaviorism is that the study of behavior should be a [[natural science]], such as [[chemistry]] or [[physics]].<ref name="Catania">[[A. Charles Catania|Catania, A. C.]] (2013). A natural science of behavior. ''Review of General Psychology, 17''(2), 133-139.[https://doi.org/10.1037/a0033026]</ref><ref name="Jackson">Jackson, M. (2009). The natural selection: behavior analysis as a natural science. European Journal of Behavior Analysis, 10:2, 103-118.[https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/15021149.2009.11434313]</ref> Initially behaviorism rejected any reference to hypothetical inner states of organisms as causes for their behavior, but B.F. Skinner's radical behaviorism reintroduced reference to inner states and also advocated for the study of thoughts and feelings as behaviors subject to the same mechanisms as external behavior.<ref name="Catania" /><ref name="Jackson" /> Behaviorism takes a functional view of behavior. According to [[Edmund Fantino]] and colleagues: "Behavior analysis has much to offer the study of phenomena normally dominated by cognitive and social psychologists. We hope that successful application of behavioral theory and methodology will not only shed light on central problems in judgment and choice but will also generate greater appreciation of the behavioral approach."<ref name="Fantino2003">{{citeCite journal |authorlast1=Fantino, E. |author2last2=Stolarz-Fantino, S. |author3last3=Navarro, A. |year=2003 |title=Logical fallacies: A behavioral approach to reasoning |journal=The Behavior Analyst Today |volume=4 |at=p.116 (pp.109–117) |doi=10.1037/h0100014 }}</ref>
 
Behaviorist sentiments are not uncommon within [[philosophy of language]] and [[analytic philosophy]]. It is sometimes argued that [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] defended a [[Logical behaviorism|logical behaviorist]] position<ref name="SEP">{{cite SEP |url-id=behaviorism |title=Behaviorism}}</ref> (e.g., the ''[[Philosophical Investigations#Wittgenstein's beetle|beetle in a box]]'' argument). In [[logical positivism]] (as held, e.g., by [[Rudolf Carnap]]<ref name=SEP/> and [[Carl Hempel]]),<ref name=SEP/> the meaning of psychological statements are their verification conditions, which consist of performed overt behavior. [[W. V. O. Quine]] made use of a type of behaviorism,<ref name=SEP/> influenced by some of Skinner's ideas, in his own work on language. Quine's work in semantics differed substantially from the empiricist semantics of Carnap which he attempted to create an alternative to, couching his semantic theory in references to physical objects rather than sensations. [[Gilbert Ryle]] defended a distinct strain of philosophical behaviorism, sketched in his book ''The Concept of Mind''.<ref name=SEP/> Ryle's central claim was that instances of dualism frequently represented "[[category mistake]]s", and hence that they were really misunderstandings of the use of ordinary language. [[Daniel Dennett]] likewise acknowledges himself to be a type of behaviorist,<ref name="Ref-1">{{citeCite web |urllast=http://aseDennett |first=D.tuftsC.edu/cogstud/papers/msgisno.htm |author-link=Daniel Dennett |title=The Message is: There is no Medium |lasturl=Dennett |first=Dhttp://ase.Ctufts.edu/cogstud/papers/msgisno.htm |authorurl-linkstatus=Daniel Dennettlive |access-date=2008-01-10 |publisher=Tufts University| archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20080111100055/http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/msgisno.htm| |archive-date= 11 January 2008 | urlaccess-statusdate=2008-01-10 live|publisher=Tufts University}}</ref> though he offers extensive criticism of radical behaviorism and refutes Skinner's rejection of the value of intentional idioms and the possibility of free will.<ref name="Dennett1981">{{citeCite book |firstlast=DanielDennett |lastfirst=DennettDaniel |yearurl=1981https://books.google.com/books?id=_xwObaAZEwoC&pg=PA53 |title=Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology |series=Bradford Books |publisher=MIT Press |year=1981 |isbn=978-0-262-54037-7 |lccnseries=78013723Bradford |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_xwObaAZEwoC&pg=PA53Books |page=53 |lccn=78013723}}</ref>
{{Blockquote|text=This is Dennett's main point in "Skinner Skinned.". Dennett argues that there is a crucial difference between explaining and explaining away…away... If our explanation of apparently rational behavior turns out to be extremely simple, we may want to say that the behavior was not really rational after all. But if the explanation is very complex and intricate, we may want to say not that the behavior is not rational, but that we now have a better understanding of what rationality consists in. (Compare: if we find out how a computer program solves problems in linear algebra, we don't say it's not really solving them, we just say we know how it does it. On the other hand, in cases like [[Joseph Weizenbaum|Weizenbaum's]] [[ELIZA]] program, the explanation of how the computer carries on a conversation is so simple that the right thing to say seems to be that the machine isn't really carrying on a conversation, it's just a trick.)|author=Curtis Brown|title="Behaviorism: Skinner and Dennett"|source=''Philosophy of Mind''<ref>{{citeCite web |last=Brown |first=Curtis |year=2001 |title=Behaviorism: Skinner and Dennett |yearurl=2001http://www.trinity.edu/cbrown/mind/behaviorism.html |workwebsite=Philosophy of Mind |first=Curtis |last=Brown |publisher=Trinity University |location=San Antonio, TX |url=http://www.trinity.edu/cbrown/mind/behaviorism.html }}</ref>}}
 
===Law of effect and trace conditioning===
* '''[[Law of effect]]''': Although [[Edward Thorndike]]'s methodology mainly dealt with reinforcing observable behavior, it viewed [[mentalism|cognitive]] antecedents as the causes of behavior,<ref name="BehaviorAnalysisLearning">{{citeCite book |last1=W. David Pierce |url=https://routledgetextbooks.com/textbooks/9781138898585/|author1=W. David Pierce|author2=Carl D. Cheney|title=Behavior analysis and learning: a biobehavioral approach |editionlast2=sixthCarl D. Cheney |locationdate=New2017 York|publisher=[[Routledge]] |pages=1–622|isbn=978-1138898585 |dateedition=2017sixth |location=New York |pages=1–622}}</ref> and was theoretically much more similar to the [[cognitive behavior therapy|cognitive-behavior therapies]] than classical (methodological) or modern-day (radical) behaviorism. Nevertheless, Skinner's [[operant conditioning]] was heavily influenced by the Law of Effect's principle of reinforcement.<ref name=BehaviorAnalysisLearning/>
* '''[[Classical conditioning#Forward conditioning|Trace conditioning]]''': Akin to B.F. Skinner's radical behaviorism, it is a [[classical conditioning|respondent conditioning]] technique based on [[Ivan Pavlov]]'s concept of a "memory trace" in which the observer recalls the [[conditioned stimulus]] (CS), with the memory or recall being the [[unconditioned response]] (UR). There is also a time delay between the CS and [[unconditioned stimulus]] (US), causing the [[conditioned response]] (CR)—particularly the [[reflex]]—to be faded over time.<ref name=BehaviorAnalysisLearning/> According to Marchand,<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Federighi |last2=Traina |first2=G. |last3=Bernardi |first3=R. |date=2018 |title=Contextual fear conditioning modulates the gene expression over time |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.12871/00039829201814 |journal=Archives Italiennes de Biologie |volume=156 |issue=1 |pages=40–47 |doi=10.12871/00039829201814 |pmiddoi-broken-date=3003983414 December 2024 |issn=0003-9829 |pmid=30039834}}</ref> the hippocampus is a part of the cognitive processes during trace conditioning and other forms of classical conditioning in two ways: needing to overcome stimuli or due to mre activity from complex challenges. However, results may vary due to the nature of the task and the design of the experiment .
 
===Molecular versus molar behaviorism===
Skinner's view of behavior is most often characterized as a "molecular" view of behavior; that is, behavior can be decomposed into atomistic parts or molecules. This view is inconsistent with Skinner's complete description of behavior as delineated in other works, including his 1981 article "Selection by Consequences".<ref name="Skinner1981">{{Cite journal |date=31 July 1981 |authorlast=Skinner, B.F |titledate=Selection31 byJuly Consequences1981 |journaltitle=[[ScienceSelection (journal)|Science]]by |volume=213 |issue=4507 |pages=501–4 |doi=10.1126/science.7244649Consequences |url=http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/Classes/31174/Documents/Selection%20by%20Consequences.pdf |accessurl-datestatus=14dead August|journal=[[Science 2010(journal)|Science]] |pmidvolume=7244649213 |issue=4507 |pages=501–4 |bibcode=1981Sci...213..501S |doi=10.1126/science.7244649 |pmid=7244649 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100702230825/http://www.psychology.uiowa.edu/Classes/31174/Documents/Selection%20by%20Consequences.pdf |archive-date=2 July 2010 |urlaccess-statusdate=dead14 August 2010}}</ref> Skinner proposed that a complete account of behavior requires understanding of selection history at three levels: [[biology]] (the [[natural selection]] or [[phylogeny]] of the animal); behavior (the reinforcement history or ontogeny of the behavioral repertoire of the animal); and for some species, [[culture]] (the cultural practices of the social group to which the animal belongs). This whole organism then interacts with its environment. Molecular behaviorists use notions from [[melioration theory]], [[hyperbolic discounting|negative power function discounting]] or additive versions of negative power function discounting.<ref>{{citeCite journal |authorlast=Fantino, E. |year=2000 |title=Delay-reduction theory—the case for temporal context: comment on Grace and Savastano (2000) |journal=J Exp Psychol Gen |volume=129 |issue=4 |pages=444–6 |year=2000 |pmid=11142857 |doi=10.1037/0096-3445.129.4.444 |pmid=11142857}}</ref> According to Moore,<ref>{{Cite web |title=San Jose State University Library |url=https://login.libaccess.sjlibrary.org/login?qurl=https://link.gale.com%2fapps%2fdoc%2fA265302082%2fAONE%3fu%3dcsusj%26sid%3dbookmark-AONE%26xid%3dba1ccbfb |access-date=2023-12-08 |website=login.libaccess.sjlibrary.org}}</ref> the perseverance in a molecular examination of behavior may be sign of a desire for an in-depth understanding, maybe to identify any underlying mechanism or components that contribute to comples actions. This strategy might involve elements, procedure, or variables that contribute to behaviorism.
 
Molar behaviorists, such as [[Howard Rachlin]], [[Richard Herrnstein]], and William Baum, argue that behavior cannot be understood by focusing on events in the moment. That is, they argue that behavior is best understood as the ultimate product of an organism's history and that molecular behaviorists are committing a fallacy by inventing fictitious proximal causes for behavior. Molar behaviorists argue that standard molecular constructs, such as "associative strength", are better replaced by molar variables such as [[rate of reinforcement]].<ref>{{citeCite journal |authorlast=Baum, W.M. |year=2003 |title=The molar view of behavior and its usefulness in behavior analysis |journal=Behavior Analyst Today |volume=4 |pages=78–81 |url=http://www.doaj.org/doaj?func=abstract&id=206927 |accessurl-datestatus=2008-01-10dead |journal=Behavior Analyst Today |volume=4 |pages=78–81 |doi=10.1037/h0100009 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20090904101644/http://www.doaj.org/doaj?func=abstract&id=206927 |archive-date=2009-09-04 |urlaccess-statusdate=dead 2008-01-10}}</ref> Thus, a molar behaviorist would describe "loving someone" as a pattern of [[love|loving behavior]] over time; there is no isolated, proximal cause of loving behavior, only a history of behaviors (of which the current behavior might be an example) that can be summarized as "love".
 
===Theoretical behaviorism===
{{main|Theoretical behaviorism}}
 
Skinner's radical behaviorism has been highly successful experimentally, revealing new phenomena with new methods, but Skinner's dismissal of theory limited its development. [[Theoretical behaviorism]]<ref name="Staddon2014" /> recognized that a historical system, an organism, has a state as well as sensitivity to stimuli and the ability to emit responses. Indeed, Skinner himself acknowledged the possibility of what he called "latent" responses in humans, even though he neglected to extend this idea to rats and pigeons.<ref>Staddon, J. Theoretical behaviorism. Philosophy and Behavior. (45) in press.</ref> Latent responses constitute a repertoire, from which operant reinforcement can select. Theoretical behaviorism links between the brain and the behavior that provides a real understanding of the behavior, rather than a mental presumption of how brain-behavior relates.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Roback |first=A. A. |title=Behaviorism at twenty-five |date=1937 |publisher=Sci-Art Publishers |oclc=881361266}}</ref> The theoretical concept of behaviorism are blended with knowledge of mental structure such as memory and expectancies associated with inflexable behaviorist stances that have traditionally forbidden the examination of the mental state.<ref>{{Citecite journalbook |date=2016-12-30 |titlechapter=Behaviorism as Philosophy of Science |chapter-url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119143673.ch2 |journaltitle=Understanding Behaviorism |pages=19–32 |doi=10.1002/9781119143673.ch2 |isbn=9781119143642 }}</ref> Because of its flexibility, theoretical behaviorism permits the cognitive process to have an impact on behavior.
 
== Behavior analysis and culture ==
From its inception, behavior analysis has centered its examination on cultural occurrences ([[B. F. Skinner|Skinner]], 1953,<ref>{{Cite journal |date=1954 |title=Skinner, B. F. Science and human behavior. New York: The Macmillan Company, 1953. 461 P. $4.00 |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/sce.37303805120 |journal=Science Education |language=en |volume=38 |issue=5 |pages=436 |doi=10.1002/sce.37303805120 |bibcode=1954SciEd..38S.436. |doi=10.1002/sce.37303805120 |issn=0036-8326}}</ref> 1961,<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Metzger |first=Duane |date=1963 |title=The Analysis of Behavior: A Program for Self-Instruction. James G. Holland and B. F. Skinner |url=https://anthrosource.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1525/aa.1963.65.1.02a00410 |journal=American Anthropologist |language=en |volume=65 |issue=1 |pages=179–183 |doi=10.1525/aa.1963.65.1.02a00410 |issn=0002-7294}}</ref> 1971,<ref>{{Cite journal |date=1973 |title=Beyond Freedom and Dignity: By B. F. Skinner New York, Allred A. Knopf, 1972. 225 pp. $6.95 |url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/004057367303000115 |journal=Theology Today |language=en |volume=30 |issue=1 |pages=80 |doi=10.1177/004057367303000115 |s2cid=220985103 |issn=0040-5736 |s2cid=220985103}}</ref> 1974 <ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Handel |first1=Warren H. |last2=Skinner |first2=B. F. |date=1978 |title=About Behaviorism. |url=http://www.jstor.org/stable/2065746 |journal=Contemporary Sociology |volume=7 |issue=6 |pages=799 |doi=10.2307/2065746 |jstor=2065746 }}</ref>). Nevertheless, the methods used to tackle these occurrences have evolved. Initially, culture was perceived as a factor influencing behavior, later becoming a subject of study in itself.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Albuquerque |first1=Alessandra R. |last2=Houmanfar |first2=Ramona A. |last3=Freitas-Lemos |first3=Roberta |last4=Vasconcelos |first4=Laércia A. |date=2021 |title=Behavior Analysis of Culture in Brazilian Psychology Graduate Programs: A Literature Review |url=https://link.springer.com/10.1007/s42822-021-00056-0 |journal=Behavior and Social Issues |language=en |volume=30 |issue=1 |pages=361–382 |doi=10.1007/s42822-021-00056-0 |s2cid=239630173 |issn=1064-9506 |s2cid=239630173}}</ref> This shift prompted research into group practices and the potential for significant behavioral transformations on a larger scale. Following Glenn's (1986) influential work, "Metacontingencies in Walden Two"," <ref>{{Cite journal |last=Glenn |first=Sigrid S. |date=1986 |title=Metacontingencies in Walden Two |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/BF03406059 |journal=Behavior Analysis and Social Action |language=en |volume=5 |issue=1–2 |pages=2–8 |doi=10.1007/BF03406059 |s2cid=54779878 |issn=1065-1047 |s2cid=54779878}}</ref>  numerous research endeavors exploring behavior analysis in cultural contexts have centered around the concept of the metacontingency. Glenn (2003) posited that understanding the origins and development of cultures necessitates delving beyond evolutionary and behavioral principles governing species characteristics and individual learned behaviors requires analysis at a major level.<ref>{{Cite book |url=http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4757-4590-0 |title=Behavior Theory and Philosophy |date=2003 |publisher=Springer US |isbn=978-1-4419-3405-5 |editor-last=Lattal |editor-first=Kennon A. |location=Boston, MA |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-1-4757-4590-0 |editor-last2=Chase |editor-first2=Philip N.}}</ref>
 
== Behavior informatics and behavior computing ==
Line 111 ⟶ 106:
In the second half of the 20th century, behaviorism was largely eclipsed as a result of the [[cognitive revolution]].<ref>Friesen, N. (2005). Mind and Machine: Ethical and Epistemological Implications for Research. Thompson Rivers University, B.C., Canada.</ref><ref>Waldrop, M.M. (2002). ''The Dream Machine: JCR Licklider and the revolution that made computing personal''. New York: Penguin Books. (pp. 139–40).</ref> This shift was due to radical behaviorism being highly criticized for not examining mental processes, and this led to the development of the [[cognitive therapy]] movement.
In the mid-20th century, three main influences arose that would inspire and shape cognitive psychology as a formal school of thought:
* [[Noam Chomsky]]'s 1959 critique of behaviorism, and empiricism more generally, initiated what would come to be known as the "[[cognitive revolution]]".<ref>{{citeCite journal | last1 last= Chomsky | first1 first= N | year = 1959 | title = Review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior | journal = Language | volume = 35 | issue =1 1| pages = 26–58 | doi = 10.2307/411334 | jstor = 411334 }}
Chomsky N. Preface to the reprint of A Review of Skinner's Verbal Behavior. In: Jakobovits L.A, Miron M.S, editors. Readings in the psychology of language. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall; 1967.</ref>
* Developments in computer science would lead to parallels being drawn between human thought and the computational functionality of computers, opening entirely new areas of psychological thought. [[Allen Newell]] and [[Herbert A. Simon|Herbert Simon]] spent years developing the concept of [[artificial intelligence]] (AI) and later worked with cognitive psychologists regarding the implications of AI. The effective result was more of a framework conceptualization of mental functions with their counterparts in computers (memory, storage, retrieval, etc.).
* Formal recognition of the field involved the establishment of research institutions such as [[George Mandler]]'s Center for Human Information Processing in 1964. Mandler described the origins of cognitive psychology in a 2002 article in the ''Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences''<ref>{{citeCite journal |last=Mandler |first=George |year=2002 |title=Origins of the cognitive (r)evolution |yearurl=2002http://www.escholarship.org/uc/item/22s8x969 |journal=Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences |volume=38 |issue=4 |pages=339–353 |doi=10.1002/jhbs.10066 |pmid=12404267 |s2cid=38146862 |url=http://www.escholarship.org/uc/item/22s8x969}}</ref>
 
In more recent years, several scholars have expressed reservations about the pragmatic tendencies of behaviorism.
* Burgos (2003) highlights the potential peril of pragmatism, noting that within [[William James]] pragmatism—widely discussed in philosophy and science, including behaviorism and behavior analysis—there exists a tolerance for anything deemed useful, even if nonsensical.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Burgos |first=José E. |date=2003 |editor-last=Hayes |editor-first=S. C. |editor2-last=Barnes-Holmes |editor2-first=D. |editor3-last=Roche |editor3-first=B. |title=Laudable Goals, Interesting Experiments, Unintelligible Theorizing |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/27759445 |journal=Behavior and Philosophy |volume=31 |pages=19–45 |jstor=27759445 |issn=1053-8348 |jstor=27759445}}</ref> Additionally, Burgos (2007) contends that pragmatism engenders a relativism that contradicts the emphasis on science as the paramount path to knowledge.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Burgos |first1=José E. |last2=Murillo-Rodríguez |first2=Esther |date=2007-06-01 |title=Neural-network simulations of two context-dependence phenomena |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0376635707000289 |journal=Behavioural Processes |series=Proceedings of the Meeting of the Society for the Quantitative Analyses Behavior(SQAB 2006) |volume=75 |issue=2 |pages=242–249 |doi=10.1016/j.beproc.2007.02.003 |issn=0376-6357 |pmid=17346905 |s2cid=24283635 |issn=0376-6357}}</ref>
 
* Burgos (2003) highlights the potential peril of pragmatism, noting that within [[William James]] pragmatism—widely discussed in philosophy and science, including behaviorism and behavior analysis—there exists a tolerance for anything deemed useful, even if nonsensical.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Burgos |first=José E. |date=2003 |editor-last=Hayes |editor-first=S. C. |editor2-last=Barnes-Holmes |editor2-first=D. |editor3-last=Roche |editor3-first=B. |title=Laudable Goals, Interesting Experiments, Unintelligible Theorizing |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/27759445 |journal=Behavior and Philosophy |volume=31 |pages=19–45 |jstor=27759445 |issn=1053-8348}}</ref> Additionally, Burgos (2007) contends that pragmatism engenders a relativism that contradicts the emphasis on science as the paramount path to knowledge.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Burgos |first1=José E. |last2=Murillo-Rodríguez |first2=Esther |date=2007-06-01 |title=Neural-network simulations of two context-dependence phenomena |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0376635707000289 |journal=Behavioural Processes |series=Proceedings of the Meeting of the Society for the Quantitative Analyses Behavior(SQAB 2006) |volume=75 |issue=2 |pages=242–249 |doi=10.1016/j.beproc.2007.02.003 |pmid=17346905 |s2cid=24283635 |issn=0376-6357}}</ref>
* Staddon (2018, as cited in Araiba, 2019) further argues that the proliferation of diversification in [[social science]] poses disadvantages by hindering healthy and open scientific communication and critique among specialized areas.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Araiba |first=Sho |date=2020 |title=Current Diversification of Behaviorism |journal=Perspectives on Behavior Science |language=en |volume=43 |issue=1 |pages=157–175 |doi=10.1007/s40614-019-00207-0 |issn=2520-8969 |pmc=7198672 |pmid=32440649}}</ref>
* Rider (1991) shares a similar concern, highlighting reduced communication between the experimental analysis of behavior and [[applied behavior analysis]]. Contrarily, diversification is portrayed as an innate and uncontrollable consequence of the environment, a natural facet contributing to species' survival. It is viewed as an integral aspect of the evolution of behaviorism.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Rider |first=David P. |date=1991 |title=The Speciation of Behavior Analysis |journal=The Behavior Analyst |language=en |volume=14 |issue=2 |pages=171–181 |doi=10.1007/BF03392567 |issn=0738-6729 |pmc=2733502 |pmid=22478096}}</ref>
Line 131 ⟶ 125:
==Behavior therapy==
{{main|Behavior therapy}}
'''Behavior therapy''' is a term referring to different types of therapies that treat mental health disorders. It identifies and helps change people's unhealthy behaviors or destructive behaviors through learning theory and conditioning. [[Ivan Pavlov]]'s classical conditioning, as well as counterconditioning are the basis for much of clinical behavior therapy, but also includes other techniques, including operant conditioning—or contingency management, and modeling (sometimes called [[observational learning]]). A frequently noted behavior therapy is [[systematic desensitization]] (graduated exposure therapy), which was first demonstrated by Joseph Wolpe and Arnold Lazarus.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Wolpe |first=Joseph |title=Behavior therapy techniques: a guide to the treatment of neuroses|year=1968 |orig-year=1966|publisher=Pergamon Press |year=1968 |oclc=6051117 |orig-year=1966}}</ref>
 
===Behavior analysis===
Line 137 ⟶ 131:
[[Applied behavior analysis]] (ABA)—also called behavioral engineering—is a scientific discipline that applies the principles of behavior analysis to change behavior. ABA derived from much earlier research in the ''[[Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior]]'', which was founded by B.F. Skinner and his colleagues at [[Harvard University]]. Nearly a decade after the study "The psychiatric nurse as a behavioral engineer" (1959) was published in that journal, which demonstrated how effective the [[token economy]] was in reinforcing more adaptive behavior for hospitalized patients with [[schizophrenia]] and [[intellectual disability]], it led to researchers at the [[University of Kansas]] to start the ''[[Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis]]'' in 1968.
 
Although ABA and [[behavior modification]] are similar behavior-change technologies in that the learning environment is modified through respondent and operant conditioning, behavior modification did not initially address the causes of the behavior (particularly, the environmental stimuli that occurred in the past), or investigate solutions that would otherwise prevent the behavior from reoccurring. As the evolution of ABA began to unfold in the mid-1980s, functional behavior assessments (FBAs) were developed to clarify the function of that behavior, so that it is accurately determined which differential reinforcement contingencies will be most effective and less likely for [[aversive]] [[punishment]]s to be administered.<ref name="JEAB2010">{{citeCite journal |pmclast1=2861871Mace, F. Charles |last2=Critchfield, Thomas S. |date=May 2010 |title=Translational research in behavior analysis: Historic traditions and imperative for the future|author1=Mace, F. Charles|author2=Critchfield, Thomas S.|journal=[[Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior]] |volume=93 |issue=3 |pages=293–312|date=May 2010|pmid=21119847|doi=10.1901/jeab.2010.93-293 |pmc=2861871 |pmid=21119847}}</ref><ref name="JABA1994">{{citeCite journal |pmclast=1297814Mace, F. Charles |date=1994 |title=The significance and future of functional analysis methodologies|author=Mace, F. Charles|journal=[[Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis]] |volume=27 |issue=2 |pages=385–392|date=1994|pmid=16795830 |doi=10.1901/jaba.1994.27-385 |pmc=1297814 |pmid=16795830}}</ref><ref name="JABA1999">{{citeCite journal |pmclast1=1284177Pelios, L. |last2=Morren, J. |last3=Tesch, D. |last4=Axelrod, S. |date=1999 |title=The impact of functional analysis methodology on treatment choice for self-injurious and aggressive behavior|author1=Pelios, L.|author2=Morren, J.|author3=Tesch, D.|author4=Axelrod, S.|journal=Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis |volume=32 |issue=2 |datepages=1999|pmid=10396771185–95 |doi=10.1901/jaba.1999.32-185 |pagespmc=185–951284177 |pmid=10396771}}</ref> In addition, methodological behaviorism was the theory underpinning behavior modification since private events were not conceptualized during the 1970s and early 1980s, which contrasted from the radical behaviorism of behavior analysis. ABA—the term that replaced behavior modification—has emerged into a thriving field.<ref name=JEAB2010/><ref name="behavioranalyst">{{citeCite journal |author1last1=Slocum, Timothy A. |author2last2=Detrich, Ronnie |author3last3=Wilczynski, Susan M. |author4last4=Spencer, Trina D. |author5last5=Lewis, Teri |date=May 2014 |title=The evidence-based practice of applied behavior analysis |journal=[[The Behavior Analyst]]|date=May 2014|pmc=4883454|pmid=27274958|volume=37 |issue=1 |pages=41–56 |doi = 10.1007/s40614-014-0005-2 |pmc=4883454 |pmid=27274958}}</ref>
 
The independent development of behaviour analysis outside the United States also continues to develop.<ref>{{citeCite news |last1last=Kellaway |first1first=Lucy |date=7 January 2015 |title=My team gets more excited by loo roll than business budgets: Work problems answered |url=http://www.ft.com/cms/s/0/a06bab2a-8ab7-11e4-8e24-00144feabdc0.html#axzz3sEMws3TI |url-access=subscription |url-status=live |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221210221258/https://www.ft.com/content/a06bab2a-8ab7-11e4-8e24-00144feabdc0#axzz3sEMws3TI |archive-date=10 December 2022|url-access=subscription |access-date=22 November 2015 |newspaperwork=Financial Times|date=7 January 2015|location=London |page=10|url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite news |last1last=Eyres |first1first=Harry |date=19 December 2009 |title=Peaks in a trough year: The Slow Lane |url=http://www.ft.com/cms/s/ec975ad6-e9cb-11de-ae43-00144feab49a,Authorised=false.html?siteedition=uk&_i_location=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fwww.ft.com%2Fcms%2Fs%2F0%2Fec975ad6-e9cb-11de-ae43-00144feab49a.html%3Fsiteedition%3Duk&_i_referer=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fsearch.ft.com%2Fsearch%3FqueryText%3DPeaks%2Bin%2Ba%2Btrough%2BEYRES&classification=conditional_standard&iab=barrier-app |access-date=22 November 2015 |newspaperwork=Financial Times|date=19 December 2009|page=22}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite news |last1last=Stern |first1first=Stefan |date=5 August 2008 |title=Keep up motivation levels through long summer days |url=http://www.ft.com/cms/s/8e995bca-6284-11dd-9a1e-000077b07658,Authorised=false.html?siteedition=uk&_i_location=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fwww.ft.com%2Fcms%2Fs%2F0%2F8e995bca-6284-11dd-9a1e-000077b07658.html%3Fsiteedition%3Duk&_i_referer=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fsearch.ft.com%2Fsearch%3FqueryText%3DKeep%2Bup%2Bmotivation%2Blevels%2Bstern&classification=conditional_standard&iab=barrier-app#axzz3sEMws3TI |accessurl-datestatus=22dead November 2015|newspaper=Financial Times|date=5 August 2008|location=London|page=12|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151122232423/http://www.ft.com/cms/s/8e995bca-6284-11dd-9a1e-000077b07658,Authorised=false.html?siteedition=uk&_i_location=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fwww.ft.com%2Fcms%2Fs%2F0%2F8e995bca-6284-11dd-9a1e-000077b07658.html%3Fsiteedition%3Duk&_i_referer=https%3A%2F%2Frp.liu233w.com%3A443%2Fhttp%2Fsearch.ft.com%2Fsearch%3FqueryText%3DKeep%2Bup%2Bmotivation%2Blevels%2Bstern&classification=conditional_standard&iab=barrier-app#axzz3sEMws3TI |archive-date=2015-11-22 |urlaccess-statusdate=dead22 November 2015 |work=Financial Times |location=London |page=12}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite news |last1last=Skapinker |first1first=Michael |date=11 December 2002 |title=Human capitalism: Does treating workers well help business too? A PwC report provides some evidence |newspaperwork=Financial Times|date=11 December 2002|location=London |page=22}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite news |last1last=Skapinker |first1first=Michael |date=9 April 2013 |title=The 50 ideas that shaped business today |url=http://www.ft.com/cms/s/2/90c6cac0-a02f-11e2-88b6-00144feabdc0.html#axzz3sEMws3TI |url-access=subscription |url-status=live |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20221210221215/https://www.ft.com/content/90c6cac0-a02f-11e2-88b6-00144feabdc0#axzz3sEMws3TI |archive-date=10 December 2022|url-access=subscription|url-status=live |access-date=22 November 2015 |newspaperwork=Financial Times|date=9 April 2013|location=London}}</ref><ref>{{citeCite news |date=24 October 2015 |title=Reinventing the deal; American capitalism|volume=417|issue=8961 |newspaper=The Economist|date=24 October 2015|location=London |pages=21–24 |volume=417 |issue=8961}}</ref> In the US, the [[American Psychological Association]] (APA) features a subdivision for Behavior Analysis, titled APA Division 25: Behavior Analysis, which has been in existence since 1964, and the interests among behavior analysts today are wide-ranging, as indicated in a review of the 30 Special Interest Groups (SIGs) within the [[Association for Behavior Analysis International]] (ABAI). Such interests include everything from animal behavior and [[behavioral ecology|environmental conservation]] to classroom instruction (such as [[direct instruction]] and [[precision teaching]]), [[verbal behavior]], developmental disabilities and autism, clinical psychology (i.e., [[Criminology|forensic behavior analysis]]), [[behavioral medicine]] (i.e., behavioral gerontology, AIDS prevention, and fitness training), and [[Consumer behaviour|consumer behavior analysis]].
 
The field of [[Animal training|applied animal behavior]]—a sub-discipline of ABA that involves training animals—is regulated by the [[Animal Behavior Society]], and those who practice this technique are called applied animal behaviorists. Research on applied animal behavior has been frequently conducted in the ''Applied Animal Behaviour Science'' journal since its founding in 1974.
 
ABA has also been particularly well-established in the area of developmental disabilities since the 1960s, but it was not until the late 1980s that individuals diagnosed with autism spectrum disorders were beginning to grow so rapidly and groundbreaking research was being published that parent advocacy groups started demanding for services throughout the 1990s, which encouraged the formation of the Behavior Analyst Certification Board, a credentialing program that certifies professionally trained behavior analysts on the national level to deliver such services. Nevertheless, the certification is applicable to all human services related to the rather broad field of behavior analysis (other than the treatment for autism), and the ABAI currently has 14 accredited MA and Ph.D. programs for comprehensive study in that field.
Line 165 ⟶ 159:
===Cognitive-behavior therapy===
{{main|Cognitive-behavior therapy}}
[[Cognitive-behavioral therapy|Cognitive-behavior therapy]] (CBT) is a behavior therapy discipline that often overlaps considerably with the clinical behavior analysis subfield of ABA, but differs in that it initially incorporates cognitive restructuring and emotional regulation to alter a person's cognition and emotions. Various forms of CBT have been used to treat physically experienced symptoms that disrupt individuals' livelihood, which often stem from complex mental health disorders. Complications of many trauma-induced disorders result in lack of sleep and nightmares, with cognitive behavior therapy functioning as an intervention found to reduce the average number of [[Post-traumatic stress disorder|PTSD]] patients suffering from related sleep disturbance.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Lancel |first1=Marike |last2=van Marle |first2=Hein J. F. |last3=Van Veen |first3=Maaike M. |last4=van Schagen |first4=Annette M. |date=2021-11-24 |title=Disturbed Sleep in PTSD: Thinking Beyond Nightmares |journal=Frontiers in Psychiatry |volume=12 |doi=10.3389/fpsyt.2021.767760 |pmidissn=348994281664-0640 |pmc=8654347 |issnpmid=1664-064034899428 |doi-access=free }}</ref>
 
A popularly noted counseling intervention known as [[dialectical behavior therapy]] (DBT) includes the use of a chain analysis, as well as cognitive restructuring, emotional regulation, distress tolerance, counterconditioning (mindfulness), and contingency management (positive reinforcement). DBT is quite similar to acceptance and commitment therapy, but contrasts in that it derives from a CBT framework. Although DBT is most widely researched for and empirically validated to reduce the risk of suicide in psychiatric patients with [[borderline personality disorder]], it can often be applied effectively to other mental health conditions, such as substance abuse, as well as mood and eating disorders. A study on BPD was conducted, confirming DBT as a constructive therapeutic option for emotionally unregulated patients. Before DBT, participants with borderline personality disorder were shown images of highly emotional people and neuron activity in the [[amygdala]] was recorded via [[Functional magnetic resonance imaging|fMRI]]; after 1 year of consistent dialectical behavior therapy, participants were re-tested, with fMRI capturing a decrease in amygdala hyperactivity (emotional activation) in response to the applied stimulus, exhibiting increases in emotional regulation capabilities.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Flechsig |first1=Ariane |last2=Bernheim |first2=Dorothee |last3=Buchheim |first3=Anna |last4=Domin |first4=Martin |last5=Mentel |first5=Renate |last6=Lotze |first6=Martin |date=2023-06-28 |title=One Year of Outpatient Dialectical Behavioral Therapy and Its Impact on Neuronal Correlates of Attachment Representation in Patients with Borderline Personality Disorder Using a Personalized fMRI Task |journal=Brain Sciences |volume=13 |issue=7 |pages=1001 |doi=10.3390/brainsci13071001 |pmidissn=375089322076-3425 |pmc=10377139 |issnpmid=2076-342537508932 |doi-access=free }}</ref>
 
Most research on exposure therapies (also called desensitization)—ranging from [[eye movement desensitization and reprocessing|eye movement desensitization and reprocessing therapy]] to [[exposure and response prevention]]—are conducted through a CBT framework in non-behavior analytic journals, and these enhanced exposure therapies are well-established in the research literature for treating phobic, [[Post-traumatic stress disorder|post-traumatic stress]], and other anxiety disorders (such as [[obsessive-compulsive disorder]], or OCD).
Line 175 ⟶ 169:
===Related therapies===
{{Div col|colwidth=22em}}
* [[Acceptance and commitment therapy (ACT)]]
* [[Animal training|Applied animal behavior]]
* [[Behavioral activation]]
Line 184 ⟶ 178:
* [[Contingency management]]
* [[Desensitization (medicine)|Desensitization]]
* [[Dialectical behavior therapy (DBT)]]
* [[Direct instruction]]
* [[Discrete trial training]]
Line 191 ⟶ 185:
* [[Eye movement desensitization and reprocessing]]
* [[Flooding (psychology)]]
* [[Functional analytic psychotherapy (FAP)]]
* [[Habit reversal training]]
* [[Organizational behavior management]]
Line 221 ⟶ 215:
* [[Fred S. Keller]]
* [[Robert Koegel]]
* [[Robert (Bob) J. Kohlenberg]]
* [[Jon Levy (behaviorist)|Jon Levy]]
* [[Marsha M. Linehan]]
Line 252 ⟶ 247:
* [[Ethology]]
* [[Functionalism (philosophy of mind)]]
* {{section link|List of publications in psychology|Behaviorism}}
* {{section link|Models of abnormality|Behavioural model}}
* [[Operationalization]]
Line 269 ⟶ 263:
* Cao, L.B. (2014) [https://web.archive.org/web/20161220110547/http://www-staff.it.uts.edu.au/~lbcao/publication/compj13.pdf Non-IIDness Learning in Behavioral and Social Data], The Computer Journal, 57(9): 1358–1370.
* Ferster, C.B. & Skinner, B.F. (1957). ''Schedules of reinforcement''. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
* [[Richard Malott|Malott, Richard W.]] (2008) ''Principles of Behavior''. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall. Print.
* Mills, John A. (2000) ''Control: A History of Behavioral Psychology'', Paperback Edition, New York University Press.
* Lattal, K.A. & Chase, P.N. (2003) "Behavior Theory and Philosophy". Plenum.
* {{citeCite book | last=Plotnik | first=Rod | title=Introduction to psychology | publisher=Wadsworth Thomson Learning | publication-place=Belmont, California | year=2005 | isbn=0-534-63407-9 |publication-place=Belmont, California |oclc=56200267}}
* Rachlin, H. (1991) ''Introduction to modern behaviorism.'' (3rd edition.) New York: Freeman.
* Skinner, B.F. ''Beyond Freedom & Dignity'', Hackett Publishing Co, Inc 2002.
* {{citeCite journal |last=Skinner |first=B.F. |s2cid=109928219 |year=1945 |title=The operational analysis of psychological terms |journal=Psychological Review |volume=52 |issue=270–7 |pages=290–4 |doi=10.1037/h0062535 |s2cid=109928219}}
* {{citeCite book | last=Skinner | first=B. F. |url=http://www.bfskinner.org/BFSkinner/PDFBooksSHB_files/Science_and_Human_Behavior_2.pdf |title=Science and human behavior | publisher=Macmillan | publication-place=New York | year=1953 | isbn=0-02-929040-6 | oclcpublication-place=191686New | url=http://www.bfskinner.org/BFSkinner/PDFBooksSHB_files/Science_and_Human_Behavior_2.pdfYork | url-statusoclc=dead191686 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120106012457/http://www.bfskinner.org/BFSkinner/PDFBooksSHB_files/Science_and_Human_Behavior_2.pdf | archive-date=January 6, 2012 |url-status=dead}}
* Klein, P. (2013) "Explanation of Behavioural Psychotherapy Styles". [http://www.kleincbt.com/#!What-is-CBT/cgzo].
* Watson, J.B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. ''Psychological Review'', 20, 158–177. ([http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Watson/views.htm on-line]).
Line 282 ⟶ 276:
* Watson, J.B. (1924). ''Behaviorism''.
* Zuriff, G.E. (1985). [https://www.questia.com/PM.qst?a=o&d=86092256 ''Behaviorism: A Conceptual Reconstruction''] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110624073146/http://www.questia.com/PM.qst?a=o&d=86092256 |date=24 June 2011 }}, Columbia University Press.
* {{citeCite book |last1=LeClaire |first1=J. |title=Behavioral Analytics For Dummies |last2=Rushin |first2=J.P |titlepublisher=Behavioral[[Wiley Analytics For Dummies(publisher)|Wiley]] |year=2010 |isbn=978-0-470-58727-0 |publisher=[[Wiley (publisher)|Wiley]]}}
{{Refend}}